My New, Improved Theory of Morality
The way many philosophers explore the question of what
morality is is very odd. I began to realise this a while after I finished
studying “ethics” as part of the first semester philosophy course at Sydney Uni
called “Reality, Ethics and Beauty” and wrote my previous essay on the subject published
on this blog. What one learns when they study the philosophy of morality is
that there are about four basic philosophical positions on what morality is, or
the “meta-ethics”.
[1]
These are typically split into two groups: the
cognitivist theories, which hold that moral utterances or
judgements have “truth aptness” (meaning can be true or false), and the
non-cognitivist theories, which hold
that they don’t (meaning they are neither true nor false). Of the cognitive
positions, the main ones are (arguably)
Objective
Moral Realism [certain moral principles are objectively, unquestionably
true]
, Subjectivism [moral utterances
and judgements are really reports of emotional states, and thus they can be
true or false of a person but not generally true or false], and the hippest
one,
Error Theory [moral utterances
and judgements are made as if they were objective propositions, but they must
all be false because of facts about our universe]. The overview I have just
given is, of course, pretty perfunctory. Something else I should definitely
mention is that
Objective Moral Realism and
Error Theory contain notable
subcategories. So, in the case of
Moral
Realism, it is not just the obvious religious evangelicals that subscribe
to the theory, but also Kantian “rationalists” and atheistic moral naturalists
[2].
Likewise, some Error Theorists
are
supposedly complete Nihilists (though that is a practically untenable position)
but most are what are called “Fictionalists”, who believe that morality is a
good or useful fiction that we ought to uphold.
[3]
Any overview of non-cognitivist meta-ethical positions
also depends on how one apportions the dogmas and what one chooses to omit, but
for our purposes we will say that there is only one non-cognitivist position, namely, Emotivism. This theory, as propounded by the English philosopher
and logical positivist A.J. Ayer, holds that what moral utterances really are
are exclamations of some kind. An Emotivist
claims that saying “That is good” can be roughly translated to “Hooray for
that!”, and “That is wrong” can be roughly translated to “Boo!”.
When you study morality in
philosophy, it’s easy to get ensconced in these positions, and to trick
yourself into thinking that they’re your only options – that you have to choose
one of them. But I don’t think that’s true. Indeed, I see major flaws with all
of them.
I believe that most philosophers
today would probably endorse moral
Error
Theory. This is because it is regarded as being most compatible with basic
facts about human morality, and the near unanimous metaphysical view of our
universe as solely material, which is the dogma often described as
Metaphysical Naturalism or
Materialism. The primary precept that
distinguishes
Error Theory from other
relativist positions is that it holds that we do speak moral judgements as
statements of
fact. That is why our
moral views tend to be immutable, and why we pick them up a certain set of
moral principles in a similar way to any ideology, and why we are able to have
moral arguments, and so on. Non-cognitivists retort to this elementary
observation by twisting their theories in weird ways, and making claims like
“But people don’t actually
realise that
we’re just expressing emotions even when we’re advancing arguments for moral
positions”. Basically, though, very few people accept hard-line
Emotivism and its unmentioned sisters
nowadays. Likewise,
Subjectivism is
arguably self-refuting for similar reasons. If our moral judgements are true when
they are sincere, as
Subjectivism claims,
that means two people with differing moral judgements must both be right. But
that can’t possibly be true, ergo
Subjectivism
fails.
[4]
Error Theory does also seem to be the strongest for more
fundamental reasons. It is seen by most philosophers, I believe, as the most
“scientific” because its proponents appear to have refuted
Moral Realism with their metaphysical arguments. Perhaps the most
significant of these arguments is the argument of the Australian-born philosopher
J.L. Mackie (whose book in support of a moral error theory
, Inventing Right and Wrong,
is
regarded as seminal) that moral properties couldn’t possibly exist in a
material world due to their necessary “queerness”. This “argument from
queerness” is very cogent and hard to deny. Generally speaking, most
irreligious people today would agree that to believe that there might be moral
properties
floating around in our
universe or in the noumenal realm (or whatever) is pure mysticism. To Error
Theorists
, that means the only answer
is that all moral truths are really falsities – that killing is not right or
wrong but that it must be false to say either. To them, the centrality of
morality to human experience has no bearing on the truth of the position, because
what matters is the “eye of the universe”. And in the “eye of the universe”, it
appears that every moral proposition has to be false – equally so for both
“Killing is good” and “Killing is bad”.
[5]
However, as soon as you leave the
stifling world of philosophy and take a breath of fresh, unpolluted air, you
realise that taking this view on morality is quite strange and leads to
injurious distortions. What I call a more “pragmatic” view on the basis for
morality, like Noam Chomsky’s (who steers clear of most contemporary
philosophy), makes a hell of a lot more sense to me. Principally, Chomsky
argues that we all have an innate moral sense, and that there are basic moral
truisms and elementary principles of moral behaviour. This belief is
undoubtedly related to what he believes about language and the infamous (but
actually uncontroversial and almost self-evident) postulation of a “Universal
Grammar”. Indeed, morality is just
like language in one sense: it seems as if we can generate infinite judgements
in various contexts from one recursive procedure in the brain. We seem to have a combinatorial grammar of morality, if you like. Possibly
corollary to this is Chomsky’s second important component of morality: the
principle that we should be non-contradictory in our moral behaviour, i.e. that
we should apply our moral standards equally to all people (and possibly
beyond). Again, he claims that everyone accepts this in the abstract; they just
don’t apply it in practice. Incidentally, most of his polemics against US
foreign policy are based on his belief that America never obeys this truistic
principle of morality. In any case, the consequence of these facts for Chomsky
seems to be that there are some objective moral truths. Like a lot of popular
intellectuals – for example, the globetrotting physicist Lawrence Krauss – he
has said more than once, without qualifications, that we made “moral progress”
over the 20th Century. I personally do not dispute this, and my own
personal view is heavily influenced by this view of Chomsky, as well as late
Wittgensteinian ideas (as per usual).
Like Chomsky, I believe that any
form of moral relativism, like epistemological scepticism, can only be endorsed
in the abstract, and is not a practically tenable position. Although it is true
that moral codes differ all over the world, the evidence does suggest that all
cultures do at least have some recognisable moral system. This points to an
innate moral faculty of some kind, most likely involving both our altruistic
emotions and, importantly, some moral
beliefs
or
values.[6] The
fact that we seem to have innate moral
beliefs is important because it allows us to extend our moral behaviour
even to actions that have nothing to do with our emotions, or even contradict
them. For example, we seem to all have the capacity to do moral things out of
moral duty. This happens all the time.
People often do things like giving money or food to a hobo on the
street, or donating to some African family in some rural region they have never
heard of and will never visit. People who look to simple Darwinian, selectional
reasons for the advent of morality claim that morality is ultimately about
favouring our tribe and that’s why we give so much more care towards our own
family and social groups than acquaintances and strangers. Yet even if this is
roughly true (and it may well be), we are, as progressive citizens of the 21
st
Century, able to see that it is
irrational
to only care about people with whom we are close. Instead, we can learn to
extend morality beyond our own social environment or gender or race – in the
end, to all human beings in need or strife, and other species too. When most of
us proclaim that “killing is wrong”, nowadays, we undoubtedly intend the
judgement to be
universal. It is the
same with rape and torture and stealing and fraud and all the other great evils
human beings perpetrate. Sure, ISIS think that the proposition “Killing is
wrong” is true only within their own sect. But most people in the West condemn
the death penalty no matter who the person is or what crime they committed.
Eye-for-an-eye retributive justice is now a historical relic in our legal
system.
Of course, the obvious relativist
rebuttal to this would be the claim that human beings are still only ever moral
deep-down because it
makes us feel good, and
that morality is still fundamentally emotional. Sociopaths and psychopaths are
not moral, they might say, and the reason is that morality is not about innate
beliefs or a specific innate faculty. As Peter Singer has claimed, however,
even some of the most diabolical criminals – one of his most intriguing
examples is the Australian crimelord Chopper Reed – still have moral codes of
some kind. They still feel the need to justify their murders morally.
[7] And
although you might think the existence of some psychopath who didn’t understand
morality at all and had no moral intuitions would impugn the notion of an
innate faculty, I submit that it would actually effectively confirm it.
Assuming this hypothetical psychopath had been exposed to roughly the same
cultural mores as other people who
had developed
a moral sense, it would prove that he possessed a slightly different
neurophysiology.
[8]
While it would be hard to prove this definitively, it certainly appears that
some kind of moral belief-system seems to be about as innate to us as language
is.
Of course, Error Theorists might also accept this. After all, as I
explained, they accept that we treat moral judgements like they are truths, and
agree that we do have moral beliefs, probably genetically endowed. But to
believe that Error Theory is the only
option once this has been assimilated is, I believe, erroneous. There are a
number of very tenuous assumptions that that view relies on.
One important assumption that
most Error Theorists
almost certainly
make (if only unconsciously) is that it
doesn’t
matter whether some moral principles and intuitions might be shared across
all cultures and communities. Most Error Theorists
almost certainly believe that the fact that all cultures seem to
accept the same elementary moral truisms and very young children give the same
answers as adults to “trolley problems” is
irrelevant
to the question of whether morality has an objective basis. In other words,
most Error Theorists almost certainly reject universality as a basis for
objectivity. If an Error Theorist
does
believe universality necessarily entails some kind of objectivity, I don’t
think they can be sure of the truth of their position, given there is evidence
of moral universality. Therefore, most Error Theorists must believe that even
if everyone believes or tacitly accepts some fact, that doesn’t mean the fact
is in the least bit true. The
proposition that “Killing a member of your own family is wrong, unless they are
endangering you” is, I submit, one such universally held belief.
[9] So
most Error Theorists
presumably don’t
dispute the universality of that specific belief, but claim its universality
has no bearing on whether it is objectively right.
Unfortunately, I can’t decisively
refute this position, but I can demonstrate that it is deeply unsatisfactory
and possibly stretches language beyond sense. My main objection to it is rather
Wittgensteinian and can be stated thus: one cannot meaningfully talk of
morality without accepting moral truisms like “Killing is wrong” and “Caring
about others is good” or the more specific proposition above. I contend that
the phrases “morally right” and “morally wrong” are only meaningful insofar as
such aforementioned truistic propositions are accepted as true. If you deny the
moral wrongness of something that everyone on planet earth thinks is morally
wrong (such as the “Killing a member […]” proposition), then you must, I
believe, be going beyond the limits of language. You are not only contradicting
yourself (because deep down you feel that it is true to say it is wrong) but you
are perverting the words “moral” and “wrongness”. This objection is possibly
quite confusing, but it should become clearer. The most important thing to
point out is that when we are not engaging in the strange discourse of
philosophy, we all intuitively know that morality, and rightness and wrongness,
have limits. While it may be possible to argue that, for the Aztecs, human
sacrifice was a moral duty – because they supposedly did it in order to keep
the sun rising in the morning – it is not possible to argue that a serial
killer is being moral by wantonly murdering people. His actions are amoral;
they’re obviously morally wrong. Everyone would accept that, and if you deny
it, I believe you cease to discuss
morality. To say that he is being
moral, or that it is simply false to say that he is being moral (as an Error
Theorist would claim) is to lose sight of what ethical words even mean. The
pragmatic fact of the matter is that, to all human beings, that serial killer
is acting in a way that is completely morally wrong. That’s how we all think
and those are the words we use. An Error Theorist says any moral judgement is ultimately false in the eye of the universe. But morality is not about the eye of
the universe! Importantly, I think it is a mistake to treat it like you would a
material phenomenon – to examine it from the universe’s point of view. To put
this in a more Wittgensteinian fashion (albeit crudely), I think it is wrong to
dissect morality within the scientific language-game. We all know, intuitively, that to deny the
truth of such statements as “Saving a drowning child is good” or that
“Massacring innocent children is bad” is nonsensical. But in philosophy it is
suddenly sensible. The question is, why should we call something a “fiction”
when it is not a fiction in real life? How can that make sense? And if morality
is bound up with the unique attributes of human beings, why should we regard it
in a way that abstracts the phenomenon from human action altogether? And if
everyone agrees on some moral universals, why should the universe’s perspective overrule us to make them objectively false?
I believe that some kind of “weak
objectivity” does obtain in the kinds of moral judgements aforementioned. Moral
truths may not be objective like the fact that gravity on Earth propels objects
downwards at roughly 9.8 m/s
2, but they’re objective to us humans, in the sense that
everyone believes them. Surely that means it is insane, in a very literal sense
of the word, to call them objectively
false.[10]
And past this obstacle,
[11] I
believe that the question of
how moral
you should be is not a precise matter but can be roughly gauged through
reason alone. Being logical is, as the second of Bertrand Rusell’s three
fundamental laws of thought suggests, in large part to do with being
non-contradictory. For Chomsky, the problem with American foreign policy (and
indeed with all imperialist powers in history) has always been that consistency
is never applied – that moral hypocrisy is rife. The governments always portray
their agenda as moral, but they never prosecute the moral standards to which
they hold their enemies on themselves. If the American government did follow
consistent moral standards, Chomsky argues, they would see that they are by far
the most powerful, most brutal and most nefarious terrorists in the world. I
believe that the exact same principle applies to all of us. If you are caring
and magnanimous to your family (as we all seem to be), if you believe in
all-encompassing moral truisms (as we all seem to), then you ought, logically,
to extend your moral behaviour to people you don’t know at all. You ought,
logically, not to be discriminatory of people of different creeds, classes or
races. You ought, logically, to try to extend your kindness as far as you can beyond
your own family or close friends. You ought, logically, to give some of your
money – if you can afford it – to charity. You ought, logically, to support
some kind of feminist doctrine – to care about women as much as you care about
men, and to rail against such current issues as domestic violence statistics
and ubiquitous internet misogyny and the pernicious effect of gonzo internet
pornography on adolescents. You ought, logically, to lament Australia’s racist
colonial past and to decry continuing endemic racism towards Indigenous people
in our society. Etc.
[12]
Although I don’t subscribe to any
strict utilitarian model of morality like Peter Singer, I think his famous
thought experiment from the 1971 essay “Famine, Affluence and Morality”
illustrates brilliantly the irrational moral hypocrisy of most of us
Westerners. Here is a simplified version of it.
Suppose you are walking through a
park. On your feet are some expensive shoes that you recently purchased. A boy
is playing next to a pond nearby. Suddenly, the boy trips. He falls into the
pond. He cannot get up and seems to be drowning. You scan the environs, and
there is no one else to save him. What do you do?
Unsurprisingly, Singer has
claimed that everyone he has posed it to responds to this thought experiment by
saying something to the effect of “Forget the shoes, I’d save the child”. But
Singer’s great observation is that most of us can in fact save children’s lives all the time, just by spending a
bit less of our income on unnecessary, material luxuries (like the shoes in the
thought experiment). The only reason we don’t is because we don’t bother to
think about these children – because we put them from our minds. Essentially,
because we are selfish. And our
selfishness also entails irrationality. Because if we all agree on saving the
boy we don’t know from drowning, why shouldn’t we all agree to saving other
children and adults in a far off land? It would, I believe, be utterly
irrational not to do so. Some moral philosophers dispute this. But I don’t
think their intuitionist arguments have any basis. Admittedly, I couldn’t
refute them, per se, but they rely on a strange view that we should trust our
moral intuitions above all else – that they should be the final arbiters of
what we ought to do. I believe this is silly. I share Singer’s disdain for
illogical intuitions. So what if these
Africans are geographically thousands of kilometres away? So what if,
intuitively, we feel less compelled to give to those thousands of kilometres
away? There is no logical reason why that should lead us to ignore their plight
and misery.
You can now hopefully see why I
do believe that it is in fact right to say that there are moral truths and
things we should objectively all be doing. If everyone agrees on certain moral
universals, and expanding your circle of care is simply a matter of logical
consistency, doing such things as I enumerated before does seem to me to be in
some way
objectively right. That is
why I think it is correct of Chomsky and Krauss to say we have made “moral
progress”. What we have collectively done, over the course of the 20
th
Century, is expanded our circle of moral decency to women, people of all races
and gay people. And the simple fact is that it makes no logical sense not to
care about women, people of all races and gay people. Even back in the 19
th
Century and before, where pseudoscientific theories about the subhumanity of
the black race and the intellectual inferiority of women to men carried great
weight, it
still didn’t make sense to
oppress those two groups
. Even the
biggest bigots back then knew that black people and women could feel, could
suffer, had thoughts, hopes and dreams.
After all, if you pricked
them, did they not bleed?
Nowadays we are also increasingly
coming to realise that it makes no logical sense to be completely
anthropocentric: a
human chauvinist,
as it is amusingly known. Just because us homo sapiens appear to have superior
cognitive powers to other creatures doesn’t mean we should have absolute
control over them. Just because a lot of us savour the taste of meat doesn’t
give us a logical claim over the life of an animal. Of course it doesn’t. To
insist otherwise, as a normally moral person, knowing that animals must suffer
in some fashion, is simply to be logically inconsistent. That’s fine, but I
assure you there is no way to defend eating meat on ethical grounds. Health
grounds, perhaps – but not ethical ones. Some people say that we ought to be
able to eat meat because we have evolved to do so and that is the way of nature
– dog eat dog and so forth. But we certainly don’t get our moral compass from
the natural world in any other circumstance. Indeed, that is the last place we
want to look for moral direction. Hitler did (the idea of “Social Darwinism”),
Ayn Rand did, but these were not good people!
[13]
I hope you can see, too, why I
believe it is ultimately trivial that moral facts are not like scientific
facts. If morality is intrinsic to human nature, it seems deeply strange to say
that, on the basis of science, all moral judgements are false, and that
morality is a mere fiction. Furthermore, it seems a matter of simple reason to
recognise that it makes little sense only to be moral to your own family or
friends or a neighbour’s drowning child, when you could be helping so many
others. Of course, this isn’t an ironclad argument against the claims of Error Theory, but I also don’t believe
there’s any more plausible way to view this thing we call “morality”. It seems
to me that morality is central to human nature and that we ought, if nothing
but for the sake of logical consistency, to take our commitment to it as far as
we can bring ourselves to.