What is the best possible society for our wretched species?
An Attempt to Define the Precise Parameters of Utopianism and the
Optimal Economic Organisation of Society for Maximum Justice and Liberty
Over the past year and a half, I have slowly come to view Noam
Chomsky’s ideal society – a properly democratic, fully technologically advanced
anarcho-syndicalist society where everyone has meaningful work – as
the least ridiculous utopia us humans
have yet thought of. Imagine a world where all illegitimate authority was
dismantled as soon as it arose and real democracy
– literal rule by the people – was
the system of governance. Terrific. And I say it’s “the least ridiculous utopia”
because the story of how we get there is not totally ridiculous, even in the case
of America. In fact, I can outline a (very vague) plan. First, people elect
Bernie Sanders, then they get a series of New Deal policies again,[1]
then he lights the spark for a massive resurgence of the trade unions, then
there is a massive resurgence in proletarian solidarity and strength, then a
massive campaign of consciousness-raising occurs (corporate
propaganda from the mainstream media is totally overcome), then the workers of
America (in their gigantic unions) begin a wave of huge strikes and protests to
demand greater control over their workplaces, then this pressure causes wage
equalisation so that eventually CEO salaries are only a little higher than
those of average workers, then lots of Mondragons[2] begin
to arise, then the economic system gradually evolves into a less capitalistic
form as entire towns and regions begin to become anarchistic in administrative
structure, then slowly the political, economic and social institutions are
reformed, and we finally arrive at “a federated, decentralised system of free
associations, incorporating economic as well as other social institutions […]
the appropriate form of social organisation for an advanced technological
society in which human beings do not have to be forced into
the position of tools, of cogs in the machine […] a society of freedom and free
association, in which the creative urge that [is] intrinsic to human nature
will in fact be able to realize itself in whatever way it will.”
Excellent.
Is this actually plausible though?
For one thing, this process would take more than one hundred years, and there
would be millions of junctures along the line where the whole enterprise could
just collapse completely. Indeed, such pitfalls would surely be present from
the very beginning. I mean, it’s not too
hard to imagine Bernie Sanders getting elected and despite what I said in
footnote 1, it’s not impossible that
Bernie could re-Keynesianise/re-Rooseveltise America without a disaster. But it’s
very hard to imagine him being able
to successfully light the spark for a massive resurgence of the trade unions in
21st Century America, given that the working person has been so
thoroughly beaten into submission since the 1980s and the very idea of unionism
has been so thoroughly obliterated. Ever since globalisation took manufacturing
offshore, we have also lost the beating heart of trade unions – big factories
full of workers. In today’s world, it’s hard to even know what it is to be a “proletariat”
or a “common man (/person)”. Are Mcdonald’s workers, receptionists, plumbers, cleaners,
public school teachers and lowly businesspeople all part of the proletariat?
Who knows?
Unfortunately, this greater
ambiguity of class relations makes it much harder to imagine a united
proletariat standing up to the “managerial class” (the word “bourgeoisie” seems
totally inappropriate) and eventually overthrowing them, even if that
overthrowing was nothing more than a gradual, incremental process of popular
pressure leading to the co-operatisation of corporations and communisation of communities
on an ever-increasing scale. In general, our 21st Century corporate
society throws up all kinds of dilemmas for any kind of thinking that could be
vaguely construed as ‘Marxist’. Is a manager at McDonalds part of the
managerial class? Is the owner of the small business you work for part of the
managerial class? Are tenured academics at university part of the managerial
class? The only solution seems to be to think about class in terms of the Occupy
Wall Street doctrine: there are now two classes, Us and Them – We are the 99%,
They are the 1%. This is an excellent slogan to use if you seek to make America
less plutocratic, and re-impose corporate regulations and strong social
security etc (as Bernie does want to do), but one issue is that 99% is probably
too big a figure. Anarcho-syndicalists definitely have more class enemies than
just the people who fit in the top 1% bracket for wealth. Are 99% of citizens willing
to join trade unions and fight on behalf of all working people? In order for
that to happen, there really would have to be a radical change in Western
culture.
Of course, if
anarcho-syndicalists did somehow get millions of workers to strike
simultaneously, it’s not too hard to imagine that they could force corporations
to radically restructure themselves into co-operative-style corporations like
Mondragon (and thence to full-on co-operatives and thence – gradually – to a
new, non-capitalist economic system). But how do you get millions of workers to
strike simultaneously, or even thousands of workers to strike simultaneously?
The consciousness-raising and union-restrengthening would have to be immense.
Can you imagine Americans suddenly all becoming radical leftists within the
next one hundred years? I, for one, cannot.
Since I am extremely misanthropic, I also
suspect we’d fuck it up majorly along the way, even if most of the underlying conditions
were in place. I think I more or less subscribe to Karl Popper’s deeply
pessimistic view of politics, expounded in his great political work The Open Society and its Enemies. Before
I actually explain what this view is, I’ll quickly go through his biographical background,
as it is highly relevant to his political conceptions.
Popper was born in Vienna in
1902, a Jew by birth. As all non-ignoramuses would know, early 20th
Century Austria was a place of tremendous political and economic turmoil, and his
youth would have been passed in an extremely unstable and politically charged world. Vienna at that time was the sort of place
where demagogues lurked around every street corner, each preaching their own
remedy for society’s ills. As a teenager, Popper rode the zeitgeist somewhat,
joining the Association of Socialist School Students and later the Social
Democratic Workers’ Party of Austria, which at that time was a fully-fledged
Marxian organisation. However, after a street battle in the Horglasse on 15
June 1919, when the police shot eight of his unarmed comrades from the party,
he began to question his trust in Marxist doctrine. Soon after, he completely abandoned
Marx’s “pseudoscientific” historical materialism. In 1928, he earned a
doctorate of psychology. After that, he became a secondary school teacher in
maths and physics. In his early 30s, while still working as a teacher, a new
worry entered Popper’s life: the rise of Hitler and the threat of Anschluss. Popper
was so worried by Hitler it motivated him to begin writing his first book, The Two Fundamental Problems of the Theory
of Knowledge, recognising that a published book would give him a chance of
getting an academic position in a country where Jews could live safely. In
1935, he took unpaid leave for a study visit to the United Kingdom, and in 1937
he secured a post as a philosophy lecturer in a total backwater, far away from
Europe and Fascism: the University of New Zealand in Christchurch. It was here
that he wrote Open Society and its
Enemies.
It’s no surprise that all of this
turmoil in his formative years left a lasting impression on poor old Popper.
More than anything else, it left him with a deep suspicion of political
idealism in all its forms. His personal development in this direction is strongly
reflected in the book. In chapter 7 of the work, “Principle of Leadership”, he
famously writes:
“It is my conviction that by
expressing the problem of politics in the form ‘Who should rule?’ or ‘Whose
will should be supreme?’, etc., Plato created a lasting confusion in political
philosophy. […] It is clear that once the question ‘Who should rule?’ is asked,
it is hard to avoid some such reply as ‘the best’ or ‘the wisest’ or ‘the born
ruler’ or ‘he who masters the art of ruling’ (or, perhaps, ‘The General Will’
or ‘The Master Race’ or ‘The Industrial Workers’ or ‘The People’). But such a
reply, convincing as it may sound—for who would advocate the rule of ‘the
worst’ or ‘the greatest fool’ or ‘the born slave’?—is, as I shall try to show,
quite useless. First of all, such a reply is liable to persuade us that some
fundamental problem of political theory has been solved. But if we approach
political theory from a different angle, then we find that far from solving any
fundamental problems, we have merely skipped over them, by assuming that the
question ‘Who should rule?’ is fundamental. For even those who share this
assumption of Plato’s admit that political rulers are not always sufficiently
‘good’ or ‘wise’ (we need not worry about the precise meaning of these terms),
and that it is not at all easy to get a government on whose goodness and wisdom
one can implicitly rely. If that is granted, then we must ask whether political
thought should not face from the beginning the possibility of bad government; whether
we should not prepare for the worst leaders, and hope for the best. But this
leads to a new approach to the problem of politics, for it forces us to replace
the question: Who should rule? by the new question: How can we so organize
political institutions that bad or incompetent rulers can be prevented from
doing too much damage?”
As this passage
shows, Popper believes, like I believe, “that we are all frail”: that there are
no really “great men” (or even great women, though of course nobody ever talks about
them), and that those most attracted to power will most likely be ruthless,
callous, narcissistic, megalomaniacal, zealous, unphilosophical, glib, mendacious,
greedy and venal. It is on this basis that he supports democracy – not because
it has any intrinsic value, but simply because it provides a nonviolent,
institutionalised and regular way to get rid of bad rulers. In this way,
democracy mirrors the trial-and-error process that he held up as the scientific
ideal in all his books and even turned into a kind of epistemological theory, Falsificationism. More specifically, the
democracy that he supports is orthodox Western capitalist ‘liberal’ ‘democracy’.
The reasoning is that democracies like England (at least as they were in the
40s) are “the best of all political worlds of whose existence we have any
historical knowledge”. Another major justification he has for being quite
conservative in this sense is his belief that we should only ever seek change through
“piecemeal engineering” of concrete social problems (for example, poverty,
violence, unemployment, environmental degradation, income inequality). He regards
piecemeal engineering as a far more ‘scientific’, rational and safe process
than lofty utopian engineering according to abstract ideals, because of the way
it also leaves room for experimentation and uncertainty. He writes, “This—and
no Utopian planning or historical prophecy—would mean the introduction of
scientific method into politics, since the whole secret of scientific method is
a readiness to learn from mistakes”. Finally, the basis on which piecemeal
social engineers should assess the urgency of problems is something Popper
called “negative utilitarianism”, meaning a utilitarianism where the concern is
not maximising happiness but minimising
suffering. He defends this both on the ground that it offers clearer policy
objectives and because this kind of negative telos is a corrective to the slide into the overweening ambition of
utopianism or romanticism.
Although I
introduced Popper as a kind of antagonist to Chomsky and anarcho-syndicalism,
it is worth observing that this pessimism about rulers, this attachment to
piecemeal engineering and this belief in negative utilitarianism, though they
work very well against most forms of political idealism, seemingly don’t hurt anarcho-syndicalism.
The great virtue of anarcho-syndicalism is that – in theory at least – it circumvents
such problems.
First of all, the
“bad-ruler” objection to political idealism is obviously defeated by anarchism,
and for one simple reason: anarchists don’t have
any rulers! Some administrators and officials are, of course, still necessary
in an anarcho-syndicalist society, but they are kept in check by exactly the
mechanism Popper endorses to keep rulers in check in his theory: democracy. In fact, an anarcho-syndicalist society would
be far better at preventing rulers
from “doing too much damage” than a conventional capitalist ‘liberal’ ‘democracy’,
because unlike a capitalist society, where true democracy is impossible due to
concentration of capital and power,[3] an
anarcho-syndicalist society permits a highly rigorous democracy, with votes by
the people operating at all strata of society, right down to the bottom. This ultimately
ensures that no illegitimate authority is left intact. What’s more, it doesn’t even
come at the expense of our technologically advanced way of life! (in theory).
Secondly, as
I’ve briefly discussed, the way we get to anarcho-syndicalism is not through
any grand “revolution” or one class rising up against another in a violent
struggle or revolt. Instead, it would be through a gradual process of relatively piecemeal change from within
a country. It would be through the slow strengthening of internal institutions
and the building up of support, leading eventually to major strikes – but no
attempts to suddenly overthrow the state. Although he might have been accused
of it by some, Chomsky is nothing like a Marxist in this way, and has even said,
“Abolishing the state is not a strategy”.
Lastly, the anarchist
aim would not be happiness for all, but something quite similar to the
“negative utilitarianism” Popper espouses, since the one polestar that would
guide anarcho-syndicalist activity is a negative goal: dismantling all
illegitimate authority. Anarchists do not aim to make everyone happy or create
a heaven-on-earth, just to make our world as free and just as it can reasonably
be. It is true that Popper generally disapproved of following ideals and
reviled lofty goals, but he himself made some kind of exception for freedom. In
a book called Unended Quest, he even
claimed that “Freedom is more important than equality”.
All this means
that anarcho-syndicalism is probably the one strain of utopianism (which I am
basically using to mean “proposal for non-capitalist society”) that evades most
of Popper’s criticisms of utopias. In addition, one fact that would count
against lumping Chomsky along with all the other “theorists of universal
humaneness”[4] is
that – though it may seem surprising – he actually shares many of Popper’s
epistemological views: about the superiority of the natural sciences in their
methodology and results, and the absolute importance of meticulous empiricism
and vigorous debate. Another parallel with Popper is that Chomsky speaks often
about human cognitive limits and the need for humility about our progress (“Our
ignorance can be divided into problems and mysteries”). Like Popper, he is also
critical of Marx and reviles all forms of idolatry and great-man-worship. And just
as Popper derides bad social science theorising in his critique of
“historicism”, Chomsky is known for his searing criticism of postmodernism and
the “corrupt French intellectual culture”. Essentially, it’s fair to say that
they both take a Humean view of epistemology:
“If we take in our hand any
volume; of divinity or school metaphysics, for instance; let us ask, Does it
contain any abstract reasoning concerning quantity or number? No. Does it
contain any experimental reasoning concerning matter of fact and existence? No.
Commit it then to the flames: for it can contain nothing but sophistry and
illusion.”
We can still rest assured, of
course, that Popper would not approve of Chomsky’s politics – not fully anyway.
As I said before, Popper was suspicious of all
attempts to move away from modern Western liberal democracies because of
their openness and the almost scientific process of experimentation that the
two-party democratic system enables. In the preface to the second edition of the
work in discussion, he writes something very antithetical to Chomsky’s view of
politics and activism: “I see now more
clearly than ever before that even our greatest troubles spring from something
that is as admirable and sound as it is dangerous — from
our impatience to better the lot of our fellows.” More importantly,
in chapter 9 – the chapter in which Popper contrasts the safe, scientific
scepticism of piecemeal social engineering with the emotional, reckless
romanticism of utopian social engineering – some of Popper’s best objections do
indeed apply to anarcho-syndicalism. Anarcho-syndicalists may have the case
study of Revolutionary Catalonia (https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Revolutionary_Catalonia)
and the example of Mondragon as evidence for the possibility of working people
taking control in peaceful unity and for the essential plausibility and
productivity of anarchistic social relations. However, there still remains a
problem of knowledge. No-one on earth can really imagine a well-functioning
non-capitalist society, even if they could imagine a well-functioning
non-capitalist single co-operative or a limited anarcho-syndicalism. And how
can anyone really know how an anarcho-syndicalist society would work out, or if
it would even turn out for the best? This problem of insufficient knowledge is
one of the biggest qualms Popper has with utopian thinking. As he writes, “Social
life is so complicated that few men, or none at all, could judge a blueprint
for social engineering on the grand scale; whether it be practicable; whether
it would result in a real improvement; what kind of suffering it may involve;
and what may be the means for its realization.” The decades or centuries it
would take for anarcho-syndicalism to become a major force is also something
that Popper would regard as a major flaw:
“The very sweep of such a Utopian
undertaking makes it improbable that it will realize its ends during the
lifetime of one social engineer, or group of engineers. And if the successors
do not pursue the same ideal, then all the sufferings of the people for the
sake of the ideal may have been in vain. A generalization of this argument
leads to a further criticism of the Utopian approach. This approach, it is
clear, can be of practical value only if we assume that the original blueprint,
perhaps with certain adjustments, remains the basis of the work until it is
completed. But that will take some time. It will be a time of revolutions, both
political and spiritual, and of new experiments and experience in the political
field. It is therefore to be expected that ideas and ideals will change. What
had appeared the ideal state to the people who made the original blueprint, may
not appear so to their successors. If that is granted, then the whole approach
breaks down. The method of first establishing an ultimate political aim and
then beginning to move towards it is futile if we admit that the aim may be
considerably changed during the process of its realization. It may at any
moment turn out that the steps so far taken actually lead away from the
realization of the new aim. And if we change our direction according to the new
aim, then we expose ourselves to the same risk again. In spite of all the
sacrifices made, we may never get anywhere at all.”
There is also the problem –
hinted at here – that even if a trade-union uprising started out as
anarcho-syndicalist, someone in the movement might decide that freedom isn’t that important (after all, it’s not an
objective truth, it’s just a value) and then rapidly amass a following of
like-minded people. The reason this could be so disastrous is that “Since there
is no rational method for determining the ultimate aim […] any difference of
opinion between Utopian engineers must therefore lead, in the absence of
rational methods, to the use of power instead of reason, i.e. to violence.” The
evidence does largely bear Popper out on this inference: this partly happened
in Spain (there were rifts between anarchists and non-anarchist communists etc)
and it definitely happened in Russia (Bolsheviks and Mensheviks, Lenin and
Trotsky etc). Along a similar vein, Popper claims that “the Utopian method must
lead to a dangerous dogmatic attachment to a blueprint for which countless
sacrifices have been made. Powerful interests must become linked up with the
success of the experiment. All this does not contribute to the rationality, or
to the scientific value, of the experiment.”
Finally, Popper brings out the
classic charge levelled against socialists, anarchists and their ilk: that they
are letting their emotions get the better of the truth and are driven more by
what Popper calls “aestheticism” than a sober, clear-eyed look at the world:
“This sweep, this extreme
radicalism of the Platonic approach (and of the Marxian as well) is, I believe,
connected with its aestheticism, i.e. with the desire to build a world which is
not only a little better and more rational than ours, but which is free from
all its ugliness: not a crazy quilt, an old garment badly patched, but an
entirely new gown, a really beautiful new world. This aestheticism is a very
understandable attitude; in fact, I believe most of us suffer a little from
such dreams of perfection. (Some reasons why we do so will, I hope, emerge from
the next chapter.) But this aesthetic enthusiasm becomes valuable only if it is
bridled by reason, by a feeling of responsibility, and by a humanitarian urge
to help. Otherwise it is a dangerous enthusiasm, liable to develop into a form
of neurosis or hysteria.”
Although this passage seems to
exculpate those who are “bridled by reason” (like Chomsky, or the logic-God and
socialist Bertrand Russell), Popper gives the impression a few paragraphs later
that all “aesthetic enthusiasm” is unreasonable and ultimately dangerous:
“Aestheticism and radicalism must
lead us to jettison reason, and to replace it by a desperate hope for political
miracles. This irrational attitude which springs from an intoxication with
dreams of a beautiful world is what I call Romanticism. It may seek its
heavenly city in the past or in the future; it may preach ‘back to nature’ or
‘forward to a world of love and beauty’; but its appeal is always to our
emotions rather than to reason. Even with the best intentions of making heaven
on earth it only succeeds in making it a hell—that hell which man alone
prepares for his fellow-men.”
Again, in using these arguments
to criticise anarcho-syndicalism, we must bear in mind that in many ways it is
a political theory unlike Marxism or
Fascism: it does not involve any kind of revolution, it seems to gain an
intrinsic incorruptibility by abjuring autocracy, and it does not strive to
achieve a perfect world, just one without illegitimate authority. On the other
hand, we must also bear in mind that it probably does have a romantic element
to it. And in fact, I personally think Chomsky is at his least logical when
talking about human nature in a political framework. While Chomsky denies any deductive
link between his linguistics work and his political views, it seems to me that
Steven Pinker is probably right to claim that Chomsky uses the central,
remarkable fact he highlighted about language – that it is a finite,
combinatorial system that allows one to generate an infinity of expressions –
in order to make a more poetic generalisation about the essential “creativity”
of human beings (as well as our urge to co-operate). Now, to be fair, I
certainly understand Chomsky’s scepticism about language’s evolution and his
opposition to Steven Pinker on evo psych in general,[5]
but I also suspect Pinker isn’t entirely wrong when he claims that you do have
to be some kind of romantic to accept anarcho-syndicalism. In order for
anarcho-syndicalism to work, people have to be willing to work of their own
accord – to experience the joy of creative labour and production, and the
thrill of self-expression – and they have to be more or less nonviolent and
more or less co-operative, once put in an environment which fosters peace and
harmony. One could argue that, once you get to the co-operative stage – once
you’re in an anarcho-syndicalist community – the environment would be one in
which altruism was fostered constantly, from the very beginning of your life,
and the ethical norms would undoubtedly be more egalitarian and magnanimous
than those that obtain in our own, highly competitive, rather vicious capitalist
society. As Chomsky has said in a recent interview, “The task for social policy
is to design the ways we live and the institutional and cultural structure of
our lives so as to favour the benign and to suppress the harsh and destructive
aspects of our fundamental nature”. Since the community would be highly
cohesive and highly equal and everyone would be educated, there wouldn’t be any
ghettos – which are obviously great sites of violence today – and you might
instead find crime rates characteristic of affluent people in Scandinavian
countries today i.e. negligible to non-existent. With an extremely robust
democratic architecture – every level of organisation having a strong voting
process with administrators and officials constantly under scrutiny – you might
also expect that it would be very hard to corrupt the system. With strong
democracy inevitably comes transparency, accountability and responsibility.
Greedy renegades seeking to hijack the system would simply be howled out of
town; they would have no power.
But this is all assuming a set of
improbable conditions. It is assuming that everything is working perfectly,
that the infrastructure is all in place, that there are no resource shortages,
that everyone is happy to work for the sake of it etc. Most importantly, it is
assuming that there are no problems of production or resource-shortages. But
there could easily be anarcho-syndicalist communities where the whole thing
goes belly up. One of the problems is that, in order to make complex machinery
and transport and so on, you still need factories and people doing unpleasant
manual labour (unless the production line becomes fully automated). You still
need some people doing cleaning and plumbing and working in sewerage treatment
facilities. How would that work? Maybe we get to assume automation for those
really unpleasant jobs – but you can’t just assume everything away. And this is
just one example of millions. How would a society where everyone has to choose
where to work based on preference (because wage differences would, in theory,
be small[6])
actually get people to work in objectively unpleasant jobs? I can’t see it.
And what if you don’t even get to
that final stage of anarcho-syndicalist organisation, where everything is
democratic and wonderful? The problems of transition are big enough. It was
easy enough to lay out a set of plausible-sounding stages in my vague plan for
the transition, but it’s really impossible to know if they could work. Would
the unions become divided? Would there be sectarian or internecine conflicts?
Would mass strikes break out into violence and looting? Would the political
class resort to violent repressions as workers started trying to assert their
power? Would there be millions of middle-class or upper-middle class people
siding with the establishment? Would a more co-operatised economy falter for
some reason? Would there be a problem with drug addiction in a society with
less order, regimentation and control? Might a self-proclaimed
anarcho-syndicalist come along who actually had autocratic ambitions (a kind of
Lenin figure) and then destroy the anarcho-syndicalist movement? Would the
movement have to be a global movement to be effective? If one country became
fully anarcho-syndicalist, would it be at risk of foreign conquest or
intervention by non-anarcho-syndicalist countries? Would anything work at all?
It seems astronomically unlikely
that everything would turn out rosy,
that’s for sure.
The example of Catalonia can give
us some guidance, of course. The Catalonian anarcho-syndicalists, represented
by the CNT (the National Confederation of Workers) had the huge advantage that
production was localised: once the farms were collectivised, all the
necessities for people to live were produced in the area. This means that the communes
became fully self-sufficient. And in the short-term, this led to what is best characterised
as an extraordinary success. As we
discover from Wikipedia, a pro-anarchist bloke called Eddie Conlon wrote the
following about what began to happen in 1936:
“If you didn't want to join the
collective you were given some land but only as much as you could work
yourself. You were not allowed to employ workers. Not only production was
affected, distribution was on the basis of what people needed. In many areas
money was abolished.[7]
People come to the collective store (often churches which had been turned into
warehouses) and got what was available. If there were shortages rationing would
be introduced to ensure that everyone got their fair share. But it was usually
the case that increased production under the new system eliminated shortages.
In agricultural terms the
revolution occurred at a good time. Harvests that were gathered in and being
sold off to make big profits for a few landowners were instead distributed to
those in need. Doctors, bakers, barbers, etc. were given what they needed in
return for their services. Where money was not abolished a 'family wage' was
introduced so that payment was on the basis of need and not the number of hours
worked.
Production greatly increased.
Technicians and agronomists helped the peasants to make better use of the land.
Modern scientific methods were introduced and in some areas yields increased by
as much as 50%. There was enough to feed the collectivists and the militias in
their areas. Often there was enough for exchange with other collectives in the
cities for machinery. In addition food was handed over to the supply committees
who looked after distribution in the urban areas.”
However,
as Wikipedia also informs us, this massive economic luxury was not enough to
make the anarchist gospel popular among the non-working class. The CNT tried to
persuade members of the middle class and bourgeoisie to join the revolution, and
discovered that the well-off were generally not keen on a revolution that
involved the expropriation of their businesses under force or threat of force
and a worker's wage. What a terrific surprise!
Of course, there is no real horror story to tell about
anarcho-syndicalism in Revolutionary Catalonia, but that definitely doesn’t
mean that the events there prove Popper wrong about idealism. Not by any
stretch of the imagination. After all, the whole experiment was over after only
a few years: both the anarchists and the communists (who were at loggerheads)
ended up having to wage a mighty civil war against the fascists. Ultimately, their
revolution was crushed.
On the other
hand, one could argue that all of these objections to an anarcho-syndicalist
transition are missing the point. There is a reason that Chomsky himself has
never elaborated a theory of transition from our current advanced, industrial,
highly technological, financialised, Wall-St-dominated, McdonaldsWalmartNike
capitalist society to an anarcho-syndicalist society where all the big
‘corporations’ that exist are not really corporations as we know them (because
everyone’s paid about the same and they are democratically structured) and
everyone’s fully engaged in a highly democratic governmental structure, with
lots of democratic unions (or syndicates), and a political structure that
involves a local democratic parliament of some kind, then a regional democratic
parliament of some kind, then a bigger-regional democratic parliament of some
kind, all of which are accountable to a fully educated, fully engaged populace.
The reason why he doesn’t elaborate such a theory is that, like me, he doesn’t know how the transition would
work, and he doesn’t know what the
final society would look like above these broad brushstrokes. Conversely, he does know that any attempt to engineer
a sudden, violent revolution is necessarily going to end in disaster and therefore
that all plans ever made by the more radical anarchists, Marxists, socialists
(or whatever) are terrible and stupid and should be destroyed forthwith. I
strongly believe that no-one should ever actually aim to ‘overthrow the state’
or ‘give power to the people’. They should just be focussed on short-term aims,
like spreading the word about the injustices of our present society and
encouraging people to join organisations.
So, really, the
way I conceive of anarcho-syndicalism – and I think the way Chomsky conceives
of it – is just as a telos for all
social-justice movements to aim for. It is only specific inasmuch as it
proposes a vision of a society with a logically
possible and practically unabsurd
system of economic and political organisation that would nevertheless result in
a far greater equality, democracy and freedom than our own society. But it is
mostly unspecific: it fails to say any more than that an anarcho-syndicalist
society will be an advanced, industrial, technological society where people are
very close to equal in terms of income, where there are strong democratic
structures from the local to the global level, where corporations are
internally democratic, where there are no such things as capitalists or speculators,
where education and healthcare are free, and where the police force is minimal
(to the point of non-existence). It fails to tell us when, or if, we should expect
such a society to evolve. It fails to even tell us that we should try to make it come sooner than is its ‘right
time’. In fact, it should strongly warn
against the seduction of revolution and violent revolt. Instead, it should tell
us that short-term goals are more sensible – that we should aim only to carry
out consciousness-raising, to spread the word, to set up our own organisations,
to support the unions that exist already, and to support the left-wing
politicians that exist already, despite the fact that such politicians will be
working for a state we ideally would like to see abolished.
I believe the
only long-term goal for at least another generation or two should be to create
more societies like Norway: strong, Keynesian welfare states where education
and healthcare are free, and almost everyone has a job. The telos that is
anarcho-syndicalism will tell us that we should eventually seek to do even
better than that – replacing the state altogether. But we should not be impatient.
Fortunately, once you do get to a Norway-like state, public norms and mores are
altered by the process of the society becoming more socialistic and just, and
it should therefore become easier to head in the direction of an even more
just, egalitarian and liberated society.
Of course, I am
not myself sure that a state-capitalist-‘socialist’ society like Norway shouldn’t
itself be the telos. If every country
in the world was like Norway, then you’d have to think that would drastically
reduce suffering and almost certainly eliminate war. Should we hope for more
than that? Should we really hope to erode the state and replace capitalism as
well?
Even if we do
want to go further than Norway, it might be best to do this by expanding the state, and creating a serious
state-socialist society (i.e. one that has eliminated capitalism). In other
words, perhaps we should seek to abolish capitalism, but do it by placing all
industries in the hands of the state (eschewing the libertarian socialism of anarcho-syndicalism, but still seeking state socialism). We can certainly
appeal to authority for this position: Bertrand Russell held this view, and he
even offers us a fairly cogent argument for it. Russell’s vision of socialism (sometimes
called “Fabian socialism”), involved state control of just about everything, but
with a robust democratic architecture in place to prevent tyranny and exploitation.
Russell would have seen Norway as still a little too capitalist – still tyrannised
by the “profit motive” of private enterprises.
In “The Case
for Socialism”, a chapter in his 1935 essay collection, In Praise of Idleness and Other Essays, Russell defines “the
economic part” of socialism as “State ownership of ultimate economic power,
which involves, as a minimum, land and minerals, capital, banking, credit and
foreign trade”, and “the political part” as democratic control. This, he
argues, would – if everything went to plan – destroy the profit motive,
increase leisure, reduce economic insecurity, eliminate the idle rich, enable
education for all, emancipate women, guarantee welfare for children, improve
the quality of art, give people access to many public services, and end war.
However good it
may sound on paper, Russell himself was well aware that state socialism would
not be a perfect system. Indeed, Russell’s emphasis on the importance of
democracy for such a society betrays the system’s main flaw: the immense power of
the state and the attendant possibility for overreach and exploitation. The democratic
structure would have to be extremely robust to continuously push back against
the attempts of the powerful to take more power and to use their influence for
censorship, thought control and so on. It is no doubt possible for this to
work, but the tug-of-war would also never cease.
In Russell’s
favour, there would be two factors assisting the people in defending their
rights: the universal education and the strong medical system. These would
probably militate against the growth of tyranny, because the polity would be
fully engaged, unimpaired, and know its interests and how to seek them.
Yet even if you
regard these factors as a kind of solution, one must bear in mind that the
power of the state is not the only weakness with a state-socialist system. Another
potential flaw of such a socialist society would be the tendency towards economic
stagnation and stasis. If
post-Stalinist Russia is anything to go by, societies where the state owns
everything tend to move much more slowly than capitalist societies. It is true
that the USSR bears little relation to the kind of state-socialist society that
would result if, say, Norway slowly started nationalising industry more and
more. In a more functional and prosperous socialist society than the USSR, the
state would have plenty of resources, and there would be plenty of skilled
engineers and technicians available to help in the invention of all sorts of
brilliant new technologies – including better electronics, better building
materials and life-saving medicines. Nevertheless, since there would still be a
manufacturing monopoly, all the products that reached the public would be
blandly identical and very dull. Moreover, it seems to me very possible that,
even if the state was working for the common good in such a society, the
overall tendency would be towards inertia. Perhaps not. But we can be certain
that in state-capitalist societies, where
new enterprises are constantly being created, and technological innovation
carried out by the state (in universities or government-run science
organisations (like NASA or the CSIRO)) is injected into a dynamic maelstrom of
competing businesses – each of which seeks to make the new technology as efficient
and glamorous as possible – that dynamism and progress are the norm. This
fundamental dynamism of our economic system is the reason why technologies like
the computer have metamorphosed and improved so rapidly, and why we have so
much choice as consumers. It may be true that this dynamism of capitalism is
part of what makes it so vicious and makes workers so vulnerable within it
(constant competition, prices forever fluctuating, stocks forever oscillating,
companies rising and falling). Even so, I don’t know if we want to throw this
aspect of our society away; the moral benefits of the progress we make as a
species probably outweigh the moral costs of unemployment and inequality etc.
If this
analysis of state capitalism as the more dynamic system is correct, and we
regard this to be a strong objection to state socialism, that only leads us
back to thinking Norway is the telos –
that is, unless anarcho-syndicalism could provide that same dynamism and rapid
change. Luckily for anarcho-syndicalism, I think it might actually be able to.
In an anarcho-syndicalist society, all enterprises would be ‘public’ in some
fundamental sense (the profits of a given company would never go above the
level needed to pay its workers, update its facilities and productive equipment,
and perhaps hire new workers)[8],
and yet there’d be thousands of these enterprises, some of them very big and
strong (but never using their size to exploit workers, because the internal democratic
structure would prevent it). So, ultimately, the prices of – say – two different
computers should be roughly equal in an anarcho-syndicalist society (both
producers are paying their workers the same wages), but consumers could make
the choice based on quality alone. New enterprises could also be set up
relatively easily, with only a little money for since no enterprise would
really have a cost advantage over another – just the ability to produce greater
volume.
All in all,
therefore, my conclusion is that anarcho-syndicalism should be the telos. Nobody should advocate a
revolution to get to it, but we should regard it as our Star of Bethlehem
nonetheless.
I’d like to
finish by juxtaposing Popper and Chomsky one last time.
Popper was really
an arch pessimist in so many ways. Some of his misanthropic quotes are so brilliant:
“The race of men are liable to degenerate”; “No rational argument will have a rational effect on a man who does not
want to adopt a rational attitude.” If I was the sort of person who put
quotes on the wall of their bedroom, these are the kind of aphorisms I’d have
on my wall.
Although Chomsky would never put such things
on his wall, I am sure he’d still accept them. Despite his reputation as an
idealist, Chomsky, of all people, must know these statements are right. As a
boy, he was victim of vicious anti-Semitic bullying at the hands of the Irish
Catholics who dominated the neighbourhood in Philadelphia, he grew up when
Hitler was on the rise in Germany and lived through the revelation of the
Holocaust, he lived through the US atomic bombing of Hiroshima and Nagasaki, he
lived through McCarthyism, he lived through the Vietnam War, he was briefly
imprisoned for resistance during this war, he was an official enemy of Richard
Nixon, and he has spent his life inveighing against atrocities committed by
great powers against vulnerable peoples, along with all other kinds of tyranny
and injustice, which has exposed him to hostility, marginalisation, censure,
opprobrium from thousands of rabid critics. Yet at the same time as seeing the
truth of these statements, I think Chomsky recognises the unacceptable nihilism
of Popper’s attitude. As he says,
“If you assume
that there is no hope, you guarantee that there will be no hope. If you assume
that there is an instinct for freedom, that there are opportunities to change
things, then there is a possibility that you can contribute to making a better
world.”
[1]
Admittedly, this might be near-impossible. Ever since Reagan and globalisation
and the loss of manufacturing jobs, the American economy has become highly financialised. This means that the
American GDP is actually largely reliant on Wall Street and trading. Obviously, America is also in massive
debt – not only the government coffers but everyday people, mainly because of
the way financialisation has transformed the banking sector. No longer do banks
bother with reserves; they just create virtual money out of nothing,
underwritten by the ‘Too-big-to-fail’ government insurance policy. And since
you can effectively ‘sell’ loans to investors in the form of bonds and
securities, there’s no limit on bank lending, which means no limit on debt,
which means no limit on house prices, and with an extremely risky trading
system full of leveraging and ‘repackaging’, that means no limit on crashes.
There’s also the problem that the entire Western social security system that
was introduced when the world turned Keynesian was unsustainable in the
long-term. It was not plausible that generation after generation could retire
in their sixties and live comfortably thereafter unless you had a stable
population and continuous growth.
What all this means is that
introducing a new New Deal is going to be really hard and, if it happened,
would involve a lot of pain as the economy struggled to transition back to a pre-Reagan
manufacturing-based system.
[2] https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Mondragon_Corporation
[3] I have
made the case for this (based on Thomas Ferguson’s “Investment Theory of Party
Competition” and Chomsky and Herman’s Manufacturing
Consent) in my previous essay on
libertarianism. Also, the Youtube channel “Libertarian Socialist Rants” has two
excellent videos about this.
[4] To
use Larissa MacFarquhar’s phrase from her capricious and mostly inaccurate 2003
profile of Chomsky.
[5] I
think Chomsky’s right when he points out there is barely any evidence for most
evo psych claims; most of them are ultimately based on assumptions, both about
the life of Palaeolithic humans and about the ‘adaptivity’ of almost every
behaviour we see in more than one culture. At our current state of knowledge,
the truth is we have very little idea how many of the traits we see in humans
today are what Stephen Jay Gould and Richard Lewontin would call “spandrels” – accidental
by-products of other changes that were selected for, necessary because of
architectural constraints on our brains, energy constraints, the intricate ways
in which genes and gene complexes interact in creating something as infinitely
complex as the human brain, or perhaps the general idiosyncrasies of the
biological and physical laws of our universe. In fact, this last factor must be
very significant: certain attributes of human beings must be what physicists
call “emergent phenomena” – i.e. systems of new complexity that arise out of a
simple arrangement of matter, like the intricate crystal of a snowflake or the
wetness of water (which somehow comes about when lots of H20 molecules hang out
together). The strange thing is that everyone
agrees that there is a fairly large domain of human behaviour that is
manifestly not amenable to selectional accounts. One obvious, oft-adduced
example is our ability to comprehend the abstract number system; another might
be our bent towards mysticism and spirituality and creating Gods. In trying to
explain the existence of such behaviours of human beings, everyone will say,
“Maybe once the brain gets to a certain size, or you get a certain arrangement
of neural matter, these kinds of things are just inevitable.” The problem is
it’s very hard to really know what is and what isn’t like this.
Chomsky thinks language
itself is like this – that it has not evolved for communication but instead
suddenly arose just before the ‘Great Leap Forward’ of circa 75,000 years ago (i.e.
causing the Great Leap Forward). Chomsky regards language as, essentially, a
system of “externalised thought”. Though people like Pinker think this theory
is mere romanticism, no-one actually knows
if he’s right or not. Moreover, there is some evidence for Chomsky’s claim in
the structure of language itself. For example, there are many aspects of syntax
that seem to be optimised for computational efficiency rather than
communicative efficiency, and the fact that even basic words don’t really
‘refer’ to objects in the outside world (unlike standard animal communication) would
seem to impugn the communication thesis. Chomsky also makes the interesting
point that the phrase “Evolution of language” is itself misleading, since language doesn’t evolve; human cognitive
capacities do. He’s right that it is extremely difficult – in fact, currently
impossible – to explain how we could have gone from a highly primitive
communication system like that of any other animal to a language – a totally
different kind of thing, with strange properties like complex syntax and discrete
infinity and so on – through gradual, step-by-step processes. Perhaps language
is just like a snowflake in the brain.
As far as I can tell, most
serious philosophers of mind and cognitive psychologists now agree that, even
though the brain does have a fairly significant degree of plasticity in childhood
and adolescence (important functions can sometimes be relocated in the case of
brain injury), the structure is best described as “massively modular” i.e.
composed from birth of various micro-faculties, each performing subtly
different functions that would not be performed as well by other modules. We
have long ago identified the large faculties in the brain. We know where vision
is processed (the back of the brain, in the occipital lobe), we know where
emotions come from (the limbic system and the hypothalamus), we know where
memories are created (the hippocampus), we know where higher level cognitive
processing occurs (the frontal lobes), we know where spatial reasoning occurs
(the parietal lobes) and we know where the language faculties are (Broca’s area
and Wernicke’s area). The reason I bring this up is that evolutionary
psychology requires that the mind be
massively modular. If the mind was the way ‘empiricists’ and postmodern feminists
like to conceive of it, i.e. a hunk of protean putty highly responsive to
experience, then that would make it almost impossible to say anything about
specific adaptive traits. As I suggested, evolutionary psychologists are
probably right about the general structure of the brain (there are probably
further modules within the big faculties). But even if the brain is massively
modular, it doesn’t have to be massively massively modular, with every last
circuit fixed in place by a genetic code that was wholly selected for. In fact,
it definitely isn’t. The brain is not the sort of thing that you could just
make a tiny change to and expect only a tiny result. Small mutations in the
genes that code for certain brain structures could trigger a kind of butterly
effect, since the changed protein would be interacting with lots of others in a
very complex arrangement. Who knows how that would affect the brain or how the
new structure of the brain would affect behaviour?
There are really so many
subtleties to tease out when looking at the evolution of human traits, and
evolutionary psychologists never do this. Of course, this is not to say that we
can’t be confident about some things being selected for. It seems impossible to
doubt (and Chomsky himself does not) that our emotions were largely or wholly
selected for, given their very important social function and the fact that
other animals have similar emotions; that our basic moral sense was selected
for; and that heterosexuality and the strong male sex drive were selected for.
Unlike Chomsky, I am also very strongly inclined to believe that Pinker is
correct when he says that male violence and male dominance are adaptive (given
archaeological evidence, historical evidence, what we know about testosterone
and game theory).
On the other hand, like
Chomsky I believe that Pinker is insufficiently wary of “just-so” stories and the
flimsy evidence that underlies most Darwinian ‘explanations’. You just have to
look at Pinker’s work to see that. In How
the Mind Works, Pinker devotes the last few chapters to ‘explaining’
basically everything about human social, romantic and sex life. He reels off story
after story for behaviours we see in humans today (Why are young men hotheads?
Why are men sexually jealous? Why are men so promiscuous? Why are women
regarded as chattel in all primitive cultures? Why are women less promiscuous
and more picky? Why are men only attracted to younger women but women can be
attracted to older men? Why are we selfish? Why are we altruistic? Why are we
mainly altruistic to our family? Why are not quite so altruistic towards our
siblings? Why do we demonise and essentialise people outside the tribe? Why is
purity so important to primitive peoples? Why do we care so much about status? Why
does love exist? Why do we prefer natural beauty to ugly cities? Why do we take
photographs of areas with lakes and mountains? Why do we take photographs of
flowers? Why are contemporary art and contemporary classical music so unpopular?
Why do we intuitively think there’s a ghost in the machine? Why is science so
hard to get your head around?) and states the answer as if it was as clear as
day, usually on the basis of what you would expect of a Paleolithic person
according to game theory. To be fair, he does have some empirical evidence for a
great many of his claims – I think his chief empirical source on human social
relations is Donald Brown’s book Human
Universals, which purports to show that men are nasty and promiscuous in
every culture, that women are chattel in every primitive culture, that in every
culture the moral norms are similar, and that in every culture we have the same
modes of thought and categories. But Pinker also largely ignores evidence that
doesn’t conform, and he also leaves out a vast domain of human behaviour. That
is why evolutionary stories are often called “just-so” stories; they just take
a behaviour they can see in the world, and give it some kind of explanation. It
doesn’t matter if there are a huge number of people who never do this
behaviour; it doesn’t matter if this behaviour is slowly dying out; it doesn’t
matter that the behaviour might be a spandrel; and it doesn’t matter that human
beings have the power to suppress some of their intuitions and their sex drive.
It should matter. In fact, I
believe this point about us having the power to suppress our base instincts is quite
damaging to simplistic Darwinism, for it shows that humans are ultimately too
complex for their behaviour to be wholly reduced
to a series of adaptive traits. As soon as one thinks about actual human lives,
this reveals itself to be true. Take the example of a Medieval monk. As men,
Medieval monks would probably have been disposed towards promiscuity and greed.
However, as servants of God, they also would have been endowed with the power
of self-control (strong frontal lobes). This meant that they could take control
of that impulse and be pure. In much the same way, the moral philosopher Peter
Singer may be naturally inclined – as the descendent of hunter-gatherers – to
be altruistic only towards his family and friends. However, as an enlightened 21st
Century citizen, he can use the neocortical power of reason to see that that is
irrational, and that he should extend his altruism out further. Likewise, a
young, unpopular teenage girl may be naturally inclined – as the member of a
social species of primate – to crave status. However, as a thoughtful
adolescent soul, she can recognise that it doesn’t really matter and decide
instead to just be happy doing things she enjoys.
Although Pinker would
regard this as a moot point, since I’m still acknowledging that the “primal”
impulses are there, I believe it actually leads to a contradiction. If Pinker
believes that self-control and reason were selected for along with the base
impulses, then that means one thing that has been selected for can override another
thing that has been selected for. That implies that evolution has selected for
one thing to defeat another selected thing. Logically, that suggests that they
can’t both be selected for. Therefore, “selected for” is a worthless term. Now,
you could argue that the theory actually accommodates this seeming
contradiction, perhaps because self-control and reason are only ‘weakly’ selected
for, and this is proved by our need to train them. But even if you grant that,
my argument still proves that saying certain things are “selected for” and
other things aren’t gives us zero insight into human nature itself. It certainly
doesn’t really explain human
behaviour. It doesn’t explain saints, it doesn’t explain weeping for your dying
grandmother and it doesn’t explain the exhilaration of listening to Tchaikovsky
(name your sublime experience). As Chomsky and Jerry Fodor have both said,
literary fiction is a far richer source of insight into human nature than
cognitive psychology. Although this might sound like classic humanities
nonsense, one cannot deny that we are
a unique organism and that ‘culture’ marks us out in a fairly profound way. As
soon as we entered the cognitive niche, we did to some extent step out of
Darwinian selection, since we learnt how to adapt to our surroundings and effectively
‘control’ our emotions. Pinker too often forgets that we are unique in this way
(and we shouldn’t forget the other reasons to be sceptical about using Darwinism
for everything).
Here’s what Chomsky says
about Pinker’s and Dawkins’ evolutionary psychology in the book The Science of Language, in which he
converses with a McGill University philosopher called James McGilvray:
“There are several
different questions here. What is the nature -- what is human nature, or ant
nature? Well, those are scientific questions. Separate from that is the
question of what role selection had in developing them. And those are just two
different scientific questions, not to be intermingled. Part of the problem
with the kind of pop biology that's common today is they're just intermingled
-- it's assumed that if there's a nature, it's got to be selected. It doesn't
make any sense -- it doesn't make any sense for the kidney or the visual system
or anything else, and it doesn't make any sense here.
There is a nature,
undoubtedly. People who argue against it for a blank slate -- that's just
puffery for a popular audience. It doesn't mean anything -- nobody ever
believed in that who was sensible. So yes, there's a fixed nature and it
developed somehow, but we do not know for any aspect of it (whether it's the
chin or the visual system or the bones in the ear or whatever it may be) -- we
don't know the answer to how it evolved until we know the answer. And the
answers when we find them will often be very surprising. So there's no issue
here about whether natural selection operates -- obviously it does -- but there
are some very big questions about the *channel* within which it does, and about
other factors involved in evolution, of which many are known. So we have to
separate totally the kind of rhetorical posturing about selection and the question
of intrinsic human nature.
Well, there is recent work
-- like, say, on kin selection, Hamilton's work -- which suggests some
plausible evolutionary basis for kinds of what appear to be altruism. But it's
pretty narrow. If you pursue kin selection to its limits, you're going to have
a hard time explaining why humans devote enormous energy and take tremendous
risks to save dolphins but don't care how many children are dying in Africa.
Something else is happening. It's interesting work; I don't want to denigrate
it. But the results that have some human application come down to the fact that
I'm going to pay more attention to my children than to my nephews. We didn't
need biology to tell us that, and it doesn't really tell us much beyond that.
And it also doesn't tell you why I'm going to pay just as much attention to an
adopted child as to my own children -- and take the same attitude towards it,
even though I know it's adopted. [Nor does it tell you] why many people care
more about their cats and dogs than they do about their children -- or take
dolphins, which are the classic case. So it just doesn't get us very far. It's
interesting work and we learn something about insects and other organisms and
something about social behaviour, but very little about humans that has any
implications.
We know in advance that
that's going to be true. Science deals with simple questions. It can't deal
with questions that are beyond the borders of understanding. We kind of chip
away at the limits.
[...] To some extent, there
are other factors that enter into it which cause it to be misleading. Many of
these people, like Dawkins, regard themselves very plausibly as fighting a
battle for scientific rationality against creationists and fanatics and so on.
And yes, that's an important social activity to be engaged in, but not by
misleading people about the nature of evolution -- that's not a contribution to
scientific rationality. Tell them the truth about evolution, which is that
selection plays some kind of a role, but you don't know how much until you
know. It could be small, it could be large; it could [in principle even] be
nonexistent. We have to find out. In the few cases where something has been
learned, it's often very surprising, like the evolution of the eye. What
appears to be the case is completely different from what has been speculated
for centuries in biology, and the same is true of many other things -- it could
be true of human language. So there's nothing wrong with sociobiology or
evolutionary psychology -- the field that Kropotkin basically invented -- but
it has to be done seriously and without pretense.
JM: There are some specific hypotheses -- let me just
pursue one. Robert Trivers suggested back in the seventies that cooperative
behaviour could have evolved among biological creatures that are often
conceived, where biologically unrelated, to be essentially selfish. He assumed
that cooperation could have evolved among biologically selfish creatures if it
were generally to involve reciprocity -- when x does something for y, x can
expect something in return. The result is a back-scratching conception of
cooperation and social behaviour. Trivers' work has been given centre stage by
sociobiologists and evolutionary psychologists. They have suggested that -- in
a way reminiscent of utilitarian thinking -- that his form of reciprocal
altruism offers the key to understanding the biological basis of morality. As I
understand your view, you do not think of humans as essentially selfish. You
think of people as capable of -- and getting satisfaction from -- aiding others
who are not kin and not even tribe, and cannot be expected to reciprocate. Furthermore
you do not think that neo-Darwinian selectional stories exhaust what can be
said about the biological foundations for language and perhaps for other
domains. Are there alternative, non-Triversian biological grounds for morality,
and does something like Humean sympathy offer such an alternative ground?
NC: Trivers' work is quite interesting. I don't think
it gets us very far. I don't think it explains why people are willing to
support the system of social security that's going to give a disabled widow
across town enough food to survive -- or the fact that we care more about
dolphins than we do about people pretty near us who could help us. It just
deals with a very small topic. It's interesting; and there are game-theoretic
approaches that try to work out the consequences. All that's fine and should be
done. But does it yield conclusions of human significance or scientific
interest? Well, not of human significance as far as I can see. Of scientific
interest, yes, but within a very narrow domain. Are there other human
capacities that enter into our moral nature? I just don't see how that can be
doubted. We know too much from our own experience and intuition; it shows that
there's a huge domain -- in fact, virtually all of human action, thought, and
interpretation that doesn't fall within this category.
Is there some other
evolutionary explanation for the rest of it? No. But that's true of almost
everything. There's no evolutionary explanation for bee communication, or the
most elementary questions of how simple organisms function -- nematodes, for
example. So yes, of course, science shines often penetrating light on extremely
simple questions. One of the reasons that physics is such a successful science
is that it is granted the unique privilege of keeping to questions that are
extremely simple. If the helium atom is too hard to study, you give it to the
chemists. Other fields don't have that privilege but deal with the level of
complexity that you're presented with, and as a result they're very shallow by
comparison. In these areas -- evolutionary explanation -- we're just groping in
the dark for the moment -- there aren't good ideas, even for much simpler
organisms.
So all this work is fine.
If you can achieve some plausible confirmed scientific results, everybody
applauds; and there're no issues. What are its implications for human life and
society? -- well, that you have to investigate, and I think when you do, you
find them extremely limited. Hume's and Smith's assumptions are, I think, much
more plausible and lead to suggestions about how to behave in the world that
are far more reasonable -- and in fact that we adopt all the time.
[6]
I’m assuming anarcho-syndicalism doesn’t have to involve the abolition of
money. I have thought through the possibility of abolishing money – instead creating
a world with tiny localised, collectivised economies which produce fixed rations
for everyone, and trade only at a community level with other communities in a
pure process of barter and exchange – but I quickly concluded that it was
highly undesirable. As I just implied, you can
only abolish money within tiny, self-sufficient communities in which everybody
is resigned to staying put forever. Without money, you have no choice, no
freedom and there’s no potential for any innovation or new enterprise or
anything. A world without money would be horrible. It just doesn’t work for a
complex society. That’s obvious as soon as you ponder it. (Despite these truths,
I have seen at least one self-described anarchist/libertarian socialist on the
internet who said that money would be abolished in his ideal society – which
just goes to show how dangerously stupid left-wing radicals can be (which is
why I take Popper seriously).)
[7]
This was fine for the Catalonians because they were living in tiny,
self-sufficient communities.
[8]
Each enterprise would be fully democratic, so no choices could be made without
the consent of everyone. There would thus presumably be competition among
companies for increasing internal democracy (in order to entice workers),
rather than over cost-effectiveness.
As I imagine it, there’d
also be democratically structured regulatory bodies – or perhaps regulatory
unions – that would prevent big companies employing ‘monopoly pricing’ and that
would force such companies to invest left-over profits into the community.
In hindsight, I think I'm a little too kind to Chomsky here. There's a nice, brief analysis of Chomsky's anarcho-syndicalism on this superb blog (much superior to mine, although the author is many years older): http://socialdemocracy21stcentury.blogspot.com.au/2011/07/chomsky-on-meaning-of-socialism.html
ReplyDeleteIn hindsight of this hindsight, I have oscillated back: I am satisfied with my treatment of Chomsky and anarcho-syndicalism in this essay.
ReplyDelete