1.
Outline
the Quine-Putnam indispensability argument and critically evaluate one line of
attack on this argument.
The “Quine-Putnam indispensability
argument” is the name given to the simplified synthesis of the similar pro-‘realist’
arguments made in the 1970s by two of the most important figures in 20th
Century philosophy – the great Harvard logician, Willard van Orman Quine, and the
great Harvard philosopher-chameleon, Hilary Whitehall Putnam (1928-2016). It is
perhaps the most important and widely discussed argument in the contemporary
philosophy of mathematics.
In his Stanford
Encyclopedia article, “Indispensability arguments in the Philosophy of
Mathematics”, Mark Colyvan gives what is probably the most concise version of
the argument:
Premise
1: We ought to have ontological commitment to all and only those entities
indispensable to our best scientific theories.
Premise
2: Mathematical entities are indispensable to our best scientific theories.
Conclusion:
We ought to have ontological commitment to mathematical entities (Colyvan,
2015 (1998), Section 1).[1]
In this essay,
it is this first premise that I will be focussing on. My examination of this
“Quinean Ontic Thesis” (as Colyvan calls it (1998)) will mainly centre on one
particular line of attack that has been visited upon it: Penelope Maddy’s arguments
from mathematical and scientific practice. I will argue that Maddy ultimately
succeeds in her argument that Quine’s “confirmational holism” is incompatible
with naturalism (even if my own views diverge from hers in several important
ways).[2] In mounting this case, I will be
simultaneously evaluating what is probably the major response to Maddy’s
argument: Mark Colyvan’s strong defence of indispensability (1998, 2001). Ultimately, I will diverge from both Colyvan
and Maddy: I will argue that Maddy’s attack does succeed in doing serious
damage to the first premise, and yet I will claim that the truth-oriented
(rather than ontological) versions of the indispensability argument, like
Putnam’s version of the argument or Resnik’s “Pragmatic indispensability
argument”, are not touched by this line of attack at all. I will thus conclude
that science does give us good reason to believe that maths possess some kind
of truth, but that the specifically
ontological question is underdetermined by indispensability considerations.
In her 1992
paper “Indispensability and Practice”, Penelope Maddy mounts what I believe to
be an ingenious case against Quine’s ontological holism. Maddy argues that if one takes seriously the
kind of commitment to “naturalism” that Quine espoused – “the claim that a
philosopher can criticize scientific practice, but only on scientific grounds
[…] for good scientific reasons” (Maddy, 1992: 276) – Quine’s confirmational
holism is itself untenable, since its overly idealised, philosophy-first rigidity
ignores the way in which mathematics and science actually work.
Maddy first
tries to undermine Quine’s reductionist ontology by highlighting the way in
which his Ontic Thesis clashes with the behaviour of mathematicians. Although it
may seem moot to draw on mathematical practice (given that Quine’s naturalism did
not apply to mathematical practice), I think Maddy shows that Quine’s holism
has sufficiently bizarre implications for mathematics to raise serious doubts
about its reasonableness. Maddy’s basic argument in this section is that the ontological
parsimony that Quine’s doctrine requires (an instance of his notorious proclivity
for “desert landscapes”) forces Quine to make demarcations of mathematical ‘reality’
where mathematicians see none. Though it is, of course, necessary for any
ontological realist in mathematics to make demarcations of some kind or another
(one can’t say that any object imagined by a mathematician exists), I think Maddy
is successful in showing the unique strangeness
of Quine’s partitioning.
Maddy’s best
example of the odd mathematical consequences of Quine’s doctrine comes from a
statement Quine made in reply to his fellow philosopher of mathematics, Charles
Parsons: “I recognize indenumerable infinites only because they are forced on
me by the simplest known systematizations of more welcome matters. Magnitudes
in excess of such demands, e.g. M,, or inaccessible numbers, I look upon only
as mathematical recreation and without ontological rights” (Quine, 1984, 783). As Maddy points out, mathematicians working
in set theory do not regard Quine’s dividing point as in any way special – in
fact, they would probably think the demarcation quite bizarre.
More broadly,
Maddy argues that Quine’s system simply fails to accommodate a basic fact about
mathematical practice: that pretty much all mathematicians are, as Shapiro
would put it (1998), “working realists” who take no notice of any considerations resembling Quine’s.[3] As
Maddy herself puts it, “Mathematicians believe the theorems of number theory
and analysis not to the extent that they are useful in applications but insofar
as they are provable from the appropriate axioms” (Maddy, 1992: 279).
As I will argue
next paragraph, I believe Maddy’s arguments are quite strong here – but I think
it’s also worth bearing in mind that Quine himself would not have been
convinced by them. As a point of fact, the whole basis for Quine’s confirmational holism was his strictly scientific/empirical
naturalism: the belief that science is the only
arbiter of ontology, and that scientific theories are the only possible foundation
for a rigorous ontology.[4] It
is therefore evident that Quine would not have felt obliged to expand his
conception of naturalism merely to accommodate in his ontology something as
wishy-washy and unempirical as the attitudes of mathematicians. Of course, Maddy
wants to say that Quine’s naturalism was polluted
by confirmational holism: a true naturalist, in her view, wouldn’t
privilege a philosophy-first ontological doctrine over the actual practice of
mathematicians and scientists (Maddy, 1992). But Maddy’s problem is that – at
least with regard to Quine’s views – she is making a circular argument. Her defence
of the importance of mathematical practice relies directly on claims about the
“success” of mathematics as a discipline in its own right, and yet Quine saw
the indispensability of mathematics in science as the singular criterion for judging
mathematical success.
Since I am more open to a pluralistic
naturalism, however, I ultimately side more with Maddy. Like Maddy, I believe it
is correct to say that mathematics has been successful as a discipline in its
own right. My reason for this is the same one that Putnam gives in his seminal
paper “What is Mathematical Truth?”: the remarkable “consistency and fertility
of classical mathematics”, which is explicable only if the abstract ‘territory’
which mathematicians explore has at least some objective contours (Putnam,
1972: 73). It is for this reason that I also share Maddy’s belief that we
cannot ignore mathematicians’ own views on what counts as legitimate
mathematics and what does not.[5] Most
importantly, I believe, like Maddy, that there is something sufficiently
strange about Quine’s demarcation of mathematics to worry that there is
something wrong with Quine’s ontological approach. (There is also the problem that
Eliot Sober (1994) raises: mathematics is not itself empirical but a priori, and the truth of mathematical theories
does not rest or fall on results in science.) Ultimately, all of this makes me
think that in judging mathematics on an empirical basis, Quine is making some
kind of mistake.
As I mentioned
earlier, Maddy also uses examples from
scientific practice to repudiate the Quine Ontic Thesis. I believe that
Maddy’s scientific-practice objections to the Quinean program are even more
powerful than the mathematical-practice objections, since I think these really do succeed in showing that
Quine’s commitment confirmational holism leads him to violate his more basic commitment
to naturalism (at least in part).
Maddy makes her case for the non-naturalism of confirmational holism through
a series of examples from scientific practice – both historical and current. Her
first historical recruit is the attitude of late 19th Century
scientists towards atoms. Maddy briefly describes the history: the postulated
entity known as the ‘atom’ had become indispensable to the field of chemistry
from about 1860 – enabling increasingly powerful predictions and calculations –
and yet a large section of the late-19th Century scientific
community doubted that this entity really existed (Maddy, 1992). Since atoms were invisible and mysterious,
and since they played no role in the physics
of the day (widely regarded to be more solid than the chemistry), many of the
most eminent scientists of the day – including men like Ostwald and Poincaré –
believed that atoms were just useful calculating devices (Colyvan, 1998: 42). The
moral Maddy derives from this historical period is not hard to figure out: since
confirmational holism clashes so violently with the behaviour of these
scientists, confirmational holism can’t really be a ‘naturalistic’ principle.
It’s worth
emphasising that Maddy’s ultimate claim here is not the simpleminded inference
that we should accept any ontological view expressed by a few important
scientists. Instead, she claims simply that Quine’s purist system of ontology cannot be regarded as the one measure of
rationality – especially not if we claim to be scientific naturalists. In her
own words, a genuine naturalist “must allow a distinction to be drawn between
parts of a theory that are true and parts that are merely useful” (Maddy, 1992:
281).
As before, it is
worth nothing that Quine himself would probably not have been swayed by this
argument. Thankfully, we can get some sense of how Quine might have replied in the response of Quine’s
mouthpiece, Mark Colyvan, in his 1998 paper “In Defence of Indispensability”. Perhaps
the most noteworthy thing about Colyvan’s argument in this paper is how much
ground he concedes to Maddy. Indeed, Colyvan essentially concedes Maddy’s
central argument: that confirmational holism is often at odds with strict scientific naturalism. Colyvan’s main
counter-claim, however, is that Maddy’s strict scientific naturalism is
excessive, and does not reflect Quine’s own naturalism. This allows Colyvan to
say that the contradiction Maddy supposedly identifies between confirmational
holism and naturalism is really a problem she has created for herself (Colyvan,
1998: 46). On Colyvan’s view (and, he believes, Quine’s), accepting naturalism
and disavowing “first philosophy” does not entail disavowing all normative
philosophical systems.
When it comes to
Maddy’s atomic example, Colyvan is again quite concessionary. Instead of coming
to a conclusion as to what a good Quinean naturalist should say about the
attitude of scientists like Poincare and Ostwald towards atoms, he merely makes
three suggestions: i) that they “were making a mistake” (Colyvan’s own
preference); ii) that “the controversy over atomic theory at the time gives us
good reason to think that prior to 1913 chemistry/atomic theory was in a crisis
period and thus the Quinean could suspend judgment on the ontological
commitments of the theory”; or iii) that “given the evidence at the time it
would be unwise to give total commitment to either the existence or the
non-existence of atoms—some degree of belief strictly between zero and one
would be appropriate” (Colyvan, 1998: 49-50). Colyvan thinks the existence of
these options should be sufficient to dispel Maddy’s reservations (Colyvan,
1998: 50).
In my view, Colyvan’s
response is really too concessionary
here. In fact, I suspect Maddy herself would agree with the last option. This
is a problem, I think, because it means that Colyvan is diluting confirmational
holism to the point that it’s almost not a substantive doctrine at all (it’s
almost verging on commonsense). If Quine didn’t really believe we should be
ontologically committed to all and only those
entities indispensable to our best scientific theories – if he instead believed
that we should be ontologically committed to all and only those entities
indispensable to our best scientific theories proportional to various other considerations, such as aesthetic ones –
then how could he have made decisive judgments on ontological questions? Surely
the point of confirmational holism is to make ontological questions clear-cut
and precise – to act as a kind of ontological guillotine. If it is made vague,
then it is (presumably) made useless.
The other way in
which Maddy uses scientific practice in “Indispensability and Practice” to make
her case for the irreconcilability of naturalism and confirmational holism is
by giving examples of applications of mathematics that are obviously not deserving of ontological commitment (on account of
the obviously false assumptions they employ). Maddy’s main example of this is
the average “freshman physics text”, which is “littered with applications of
mathematics that are expressly understood not to be literally true: e.g., the
analysis of water waves by assuming the water to be infinitely deep or the
treatment of matter as continuous in fluid dynamics or the representation of
energy as a continuously varying quantity” (Maddy, 1992: 281). The
indispensability of such unrealistic mathematical tools is not in dispute, and
yet only an insane person would think that that fact is sufficient to
ontologically commit us to the mathematical objects required by these
mathematical tools.
I think Maddy’s attack
here succeeds in inflicting yet more damage on Quine’s confirmational holism, though
I also believe that Maddy misses an opportunity in this passage to invoke the
plentiful applications of unrealistic mathematics in economics – a field which did (surprisingly) fall under Quine’s
very broad conception of science (Quine, 1995: 49). As anyone who has read a
freshman economics text realises, neoclassical
economics uses highly simplified, toy models of the real world, and typically
eschews dynamic modelling – instead making totally unrealistic assumptions
about tendencies towards “equilibrium”. And just as with physics, nobody would
say that we should be ontologically
committed to the mathematical entities needed for these models.
The way Colyvan
replies to this latter class of Maddy examples in “In Defence of
Indispensability” is, again, not to deny their validity, but simply to claim
that scientists often do worry about
the ontology of the mathematics they are using – thus proving that it is certainly
not anything goes. Colyvan’s example
of useful maths that was viewed with suspicion by scientists is the Dirac delta
function. This strange mathematical object proved very useful in quantum
mechanics, and yet, as Colyvan notes, it “attracted much criticism” (Colyvan,
1998: 52).
It’s worth
nothing that Colyvan is once again making massive concessions here. He has
strayed so far from the literal Quine Ontic Thesis and the literal doctrine of
confirmational holism that he is looking for evidence of scientists not taking confirmational
holism too seriously (by being suspicious of the ontology of indispensable
mathematics) in order to show that some enervated version of confirmational
holism is still possible. It’s a strange position, in my opinion.
All in all, my
conclusion about Maddy’s attack on the first premise of the Quinean
indispensability argument is that it is broadly successful. As I’ve made clear,
I think Maddy’s success is even evident in Mark Colyvan’s attempt to defend the premise, since Colyvan’s
defence involves diluting the doctrine of confirmational holism to such an
extent that it basically loses all meaning. Though I haven’t mentioned this
philosopher so far, I also think that Maddy’s critique is boosted by some of
the observations of Stephen Yablo (1998) about the ineliminably metaphorical
nature of a lot of the language in our best scientific theories. As Yablo
notes, Quine never adequately acknowledged the importance of figurative
language in our scientific discourse, and this is reflected in the rigidity of
the doctrine of confirmational holism.[6]
As I suggested
in my introduction, I certainly don’t think that there isn’t some salvageable form of the
indispensability argument. Indeed, I think the truth-oriented versions of the argument
are totally unassailable. One example of such an argument is Michael Resnik’s
“Pragmatic Indispensability Argument”, laid out in his book Mathematics as a Science of Patterns. Resnik’s
formulation doesn’t rely on confirmational holism, and thus doesn’t have a
premise nearly as strong as the Quine Ontic Thesis. Instead, its two key
premises are that “We are justified in drawing conclusions from and within
science only if we are justified in taking the mathematics used in science to
be true” and “We are justified in using science to explain and predict”
(Resnik, 1997: 47). The idea is that science’s success only makes sense if the
mathematics used in it is largely or wholly true.
I personally see
no way of denying this argument. As I made clear in footnote 1, Putnam also
made a similar truth-oriented argument, and was generally less rigid about
ontology than Quine, holding no such doctrine as confirmational holism. This
makes his indispensability arguments
more attractive, in my view.
Bibliography
Colyvan, Mark (1998). “In Defence of Indispensability”, Philosophia Mathematica, 6 (1): 39-62.
(2001). The
Indispensability of Mathematics, Oxford University Press.
Maddy, Penelope (1992). “Indispensability and practice”, Journal of Philosophy, 89 (6): 275-289.
Putnam, Hilary (1975). “What is Mathematical Truth?”, in Mathematics, Matter and Method, Cambridge
University Press 60--78.
Quine, Willard van Orman (1961). “On What There Is”, in Tim Crane
& Katalin Farkas (eds.), From a
Logical Point of View, Harvard University Press, 21-38.
(1995). From Stimulus
to Science, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass.
Resnik, Michael (1997). Mathematics
as a Science of Patterns, Oxford University Press.
Shapiro, Stewart (1996). The
Philosophy of Mathematics: Structure and Ontology, Oxford University Press.
Yablo, Stephen (1998). “Does Ontology Rest on a Mistake?”, Aristotelian
Society Supplementary Volume, 72 (1): 229 - 283.
[1] It
should be noted that this formulation is very Quine-biased, and doesn’t very
well capture Putnam’s
indispensability arguments. In fact, Putnam criticises Colyvan’s formulation
directly in chapter 9 of the 2012 book Philosophy
in an Age of Science: “From my point of view, Colyvan’s description of my
argument(s) is far from right” (Putnam, 2014: 1). Putnam’s objections to the formulation are
several. Firstly, it doesn’t capture the important distinctions between his and
Quine’s views: “The fact is
that in “What is Mathematical Truth” I argued that the internal success and coherence of mathematics is evidence that
it is true under some interpretation,
and that its indispensability for physics
is evidence that it is true under a realist
interpretation” […] “a distinction that Quine nowhere draws” (Putnam, 2014: 2). Secondly, Putnam points out that he never
argued for anything as straightforward as “ontological commitment” to objects
or entities (and was never a “Platonist” per se): in both “What Is Mathematical
Truth?” and “Mathematics Without Foundations”, he “said that set theory did not
have to be interpreted Platonistically” and that “modal-logical mathematics
(i.e. mathematics which takes mathematical possibility as primitive and not
abstract entities of any kind) and mathematics which takes sets as primitive
are “equivalent descriptions”” (Putnam, 2014: 2). Whereas Putnam’s “indispensability” argument was – as
he puts it – “an argument for the objectivity
of mathematics in a realist sense—i.e. for the idea that mathematical truth
must not be identified with provability”,
Quine’s indispensability argument was an “argument for “reluctant
Platonism,” which he himself characterized as accepting the existence of
“intangible objects” (numbers and sets)” (Putnam, 2014: 2). Finally, Putnam
never subscribed to the “and only” part of the first premise (Putnam, 2014: 3).
Despite all these problems with the
formulation, it is Colyvan’s exposition of the argument that I will be
attacking in my essay. One good reason for sticking with this Quine-biased
formulation is that most of the literature on the ‘Quine-Putnam
indispensability argument’ is also Quine-biased.
[2]
‘Confirmational holism’ is a slightly misleading name for Quine’s mechanical
system of ontology. In essence, it refers to Quine’s claim, famously expressed
in his essay “On What There Is”, that a scientific theory is “committed to those and only those entities
to which the bound variables of the theory must be capable of referring in order
that the affirmations made in the theory be true” (Quine, 1943: 33).
The key feature of this
doctrine is its rigidity. According to Quine, if a new grand theory of physics
were to come along that bettered our current Relativity/quantum mechanics
synthesis in terms of explanatory accuracy, predictive power, ontological
parsimony (and so on), we should immediately abandon all ontological commitments
to entities that aren’t necessary for the truth of the affirmations of the new
theory and immediately adopt ontological commitments to all and only the entities
that are. (It’s clear why I called it a “mechanical system of ontology”.)
[3] Hilbert
was unusual (and his program failed anyway).
[4] We
will later see that Colyvan, a neo-Quinean, also defends this view (1998,
2001).
[5]
Note, however, that I am not endorsing Maddy’s own ontology. I have as yet said
nothing about whether any mathematical “objects” “exist”.
[6] As
Yablo writes in “Does Ontology Rest on a Mistake?”, “Intentional attributions, subjunctive
conditionals, and so on are said [by Quine] to have ‘no place in an austere canonical
notation for science’ suitable for ‘limning the true and ultimate structure of
reality’”.
No comments:
Post a Comment