Singer and the Evolution of Altruism
Biological
Assumptions in Peter Singer’s Ethics and
Intuitions:
In this 2005
paper, Peter Singer uses decades-old research in theoretical evolutionary
biology and some recent results in cognitive psychology and neuroscience to
argue that we should, in general, be highly suspicious of our intuitions when
engaging in moral reasoning, since they will tend to lead us astray from the
impartial application of abstract moral principles in favour of philosophically
indefensible ‘gut’ reactions.
In the first section of the paper, Singer argues that modern science
backs up many of the bleak descriptions of ‘human nature’ contained in the
works of Enlightenment philosophers like David Hume and Thomas Hobbes. Singer begins
the section by praising the following conjecture of Hume’s: “A man naturally
loves his children better than his nephews, his nephews better than his
cousins, his cousins better than strangers, where every thing else is equal” [Hume,
1739/1896: 251; Singer: 334]. Singer takes for granted that this is an accurate
observation, and gestures towards the Hamiltonian/Dawkinsian, gene-centric kin selection theory of altruism as the
explanation for it. Next, Singer begins to make some vaguely-scientifically-tethered
claims about prehistory: à la Hobbes, Singer asserts that early human life was “more
often a struggle for survival between different human beings” than a struggle
against other species [335]. This leads him onto a (once more) unsourced
account of the most general evolutionary theory for the origin of extra-genetic
altruism, reciprocal altruism; in
particular, he claims that “Many features of human morality could have grown
out of simple reciprocal practices such as the mutual removal of parasites from
awkward places” [336].
Finally, he refers to the empirical work of Jonathan Haidt on moral
rationalisation, and Joshua Greene’s very well-publicised studies on the
Trolley Problem, along with some neuroscientific studies about the link between
abnormalities in the prefrontal cortex and “anti-social behaviour”, to make
clear that there is a strong emotional element to the way we typically make
moral judgments, and no sense in which our intuitions are based on consistent
application of principle [339].
Singer uses all these considerations from disparate areas of scientific
inquiry for a methodological conclusion about moral philosophy: specifically,
he opposes his stance against John Rawls’ (fairly middle-ground) methodological
approach to moral reasoning, the principle of “reflective equilibrium” pioneered
in A Theory of Justice. Reflective
equilibrium is, in Singer’s words, the principle that “where there is no
inherently plausible theory that perfectly matches our initial moral judgments,
we should modify either the theory, or the judgments, until we have an
equilibrium between the two” [344]. Singer disagrees with this because he
thinks that it is often most rational often to ignore entirely our
pre-theoretic judgments (intuitions) when we encounter a moral dilemma. He
thinks that we should concern ourselves only
with applying the “plausible theory” (he more or less ignores the
complication that a moral theory wouldn’t be plausible in any sense if it ran
totally against our moral emotions). Crucially, he thinks the science lends a
lot of support to this methodological conclusion, since it shows that our intuitions
are not useful “data” when it comes to the process of rigorously reasoning
about what we ought to do, and lead us instead towards ethical ‘parochialisms’ and
inconsistencies.
Two Scientific Papers Examining
Evolutionary (including Multi-Level Selection)_Theories of Co-operation:
1.)
“Human Co-operation” (2013), by David Rand and Martin Nowak.
This paper is a discursive review of laboratory experiments
and field studies of human behaviour by a Yale cognitive scientist (Rand) and a
Harvard evolutionary biologist and mathematician (Nowak). It focusses on how
the empirical evidence bears on the relative strength of the five mechanisms
proposed to explain the evolution of human co-operation: direct reciprocity,
indirect reciprocity, spatial selection, multilevel selection, and kin
selection. The discussion in this paper relates directly to the vague
scientific references made by Singer towards theoretical evolutionary biology,
and his apparent belief that kin selection and direct reciprocity are the only
games in town.
In their very diplomatic treatment of
the evidence supporting each of the five mechanisms, Rand and Nowak seem to
suggest that there is good reason to suppose that all five mechanisms have played a role in the evolution of human
co-operation. Their analysis therefore doesn’t seem to support more hegemonic
views: for example, Hume’s strong claim about the disproportionate power of
familial affection (at least if “love” is interpreted in the broad sense that
Singer himself seems to want to interpret it). In fact, as Rand and Nowak
discuss in the section on multilevel selection, it has been experimentally shown
that unrelated strangers can be readily
induced to co-operate effectively with each other simply if they are told
they now ‘belong to a team’ in competition with another [Rand and Nowak,
419-420].
Singer, of course, is aware of
research on the power of group-loyalty and tribalism, as evinced by his
references to Jonathan Haidt. However, he seemed unware (in 2005) that this
well-studied phenomenon actually constitutes very good evidence for a kind of
(probably cultural) group selection towards within-group co-operation, thus
undermining purely gene-centric views about the evolution of human co-operation
(which tend to downplay the existence of widespread human co-operation).
2.) “The evolution of extreme cooperation
via shared dysphoric experiences” (2017), by Harvey Whitehouse et al (12
contributors).
This paper is a recent interdisciplinary research article
in Nature in which the authors lay
out a new mathematical model which they claim shows how “conditioning
cooperation on previous shared experience can allow individually costly
pro-group behavior to evolve”, with evidence provided in the form of the
testing of the predictions of the model in a range of sample populations
(including military veterans, college fraternity/sorority members, football
fans, martial arts practitioners, and twins) [1]. Overall, they obtain strong
support for the conclusion “that shared dysphoric experiences are a powerful
mechanism for promoting pro-group behaviors which under certain conditions can
be extremely costly to the individuals concerned” [6].
This finding doesn’t directly
undermine Singer’s biological assumptions in any direct way, although the
explanadum of the paper’s thesis (that humans sometimes engage in pro-group
behaviours which are “extremely costly to the individuals concerned” (like
suicide terrorism and fighting for ‘king and country’ in deadly conflicts [1]))
is something that Singer’s human-nature-related assertions in Ethics and Intuitions completely miss
out. Furthermore, one subsidiary empirical
conclusion of the article, used as evidence against the notion that
self-sacrifice for the group can be fully explained by the so-called
“psychological kin” phenomenon, does directly undermine one of Singer’s claims:
namely, the Humean one. As the authors
point out early in the piece, a recent survey of participants in the Libyan
uprising of 2011, thousands of whom died in combat, found that “frontline
fighters were more likely to choose genetically unrelated fellow
revolutionaries in preference to family as the group with which they are most
fused” [2].
Singer would probably argue that,
though these new results do impugn some parts of his generally vague scientific
discussion in Ethics and Intuitions, they
do not undermine the view that our moral “intuitions” can steer us away from a
more rational and universalised morality. Indeed, the idea that powerful,
large-scale co-operation tends to be group-based and highly context-dependent,
typically reliant on extreme events and highly dependent on the existence of enemy groups, only lends support to the
general thesis that we should try our best to transcend our more immediate
moral emotions in favour of the application of general principles. On the other
hand, it may be that Singer’s own distorted cognitive science has misled him as
to the real-world plausibility of a co-operative and altruistic ethic which
doesn’t rely psychologically on some kind of group identification. Singer may
well overlook the extent to which even non-parochial moral systems rely on the
commandeering of group-based moral sentiments; for example, achieving a
successful ‘expansion of the circle’ may require the stigmatisation of those
who don’t.
Bibliography
Rand, D.G. and
Nowak, M.A. “Human cooperation”, Trends
in Cognitive Sciences, Vol. 17: 8, August 2013, pp. 413-425.
[Google
citations: 348; Journal Citation Reports lists its 2013 Impact
Factor at 21.147.]
Singer, P.J. “Ethics and Intuitions”, The Journal of Ethics, Vol. 9: 3,
October 2005, pp. 331-352.
[Google citations: 460; Impact Factor of journal:
unavailable].
Whitehouse, H, et al. “The evolution of
extreme cooperation via shared dysphoric experiences”, Nature: Scientific Reports, 7, Article number: 44292, February 2017.
[Google citations: 1; Impact Factor of
journal: 5.228.]
No comments:
Post a Comment