Ethics of Abortion Redux
I support lenient abortion laws. I think that we should
minimise the obstacles placed in the way of safe abortions at clinics.
Nevertheless, unlike the majority of liberals and leftists, I don't think the
ethics of abortion are clear-cut. I am right and they are wrong: the vast majority
of liberals and leftists haven't thought very hard about the ethics of abortion
(not surprising, given that very few people think hard about anything). I think
it's obvious to anyone familiar with the argument of Don Marquis – a cruder
version of which I came to independently, and wrote about in an old essay (published
in September 2015) called "Deep Moral Dilemmas and the Futility of
Formalisation" – that the matter is not straightforward. I will explain my
reasons for supporting lenient abortion laws despite this much later on. But
for now I will explain why the question of the morality of abortion is tricky,
and why much of what "pro-choice" advocates say about abortion is as
unrigorous as the religious malarkey of the "pro-lifers".
A lot (probably most) of what
pro-choice progressives say about abortion is pure BS. Most pro-choice
progressives seem convinced that, once you abandon religion, there is no argument
whatsoever. This leads them to treat slogans like “Men would never tolerate
having their reproductive rights infringed" as trump cards – obvious proof
of male hypocrisy and the persistence of patriarchal domination within our
society. Similarly, it leads them to see memes like that doctored image of Hillary
Clinton, surrounded by women, signing away men’s right to ejaculate outside of
reproduction, as rational takedowns. The problem is that one can only see the
exertion of legislative control over abortion as unambiguous male hypocrisy if
you presuppose that the analogy is completely clear – that there is not a hint of
a morally relevant difference – between the reproductive role of females and
the reproductive role of males. But the analogy is clearly not clear: as we all
know, females incubate proto-human beings whereas males produce only gametes.
And, as I will later argue, that is indeed a morally relevant difference.
A similar line that one often
hears is the following: “If men had uteruses, there’s no way they’d be signing
such draconian laws”. The problem with this slogan is that if men had uteruses and
didn’t make such laws, then it’s hard to see in what sense they’d still be men.
In fact, the sentence verges on total nonsense. It is essentially impossible to
analyse the sentence in a way that makes any sense. This is the best I’ve got: “If you imagine a
world identical to our own, but except for the male (biological) sex there is a
different sex which has the psychology of biological males in our current world
and dominates the highest levels of government and business in the way that
males do in our current world, but which reproduces in the way females do (and
this would, of course, also mean that this sex has a vagina and ovaries and big
breasts for lactating and wide hips for giving birth and that this sex ovulates,
which would mean an entire different evolutionary history (which would mean
that this sex looks like females in our current world in every possible way
(gracile facial features, less body hair, etc), and would, of course, mean that
the “women” in this world would have to be sexually male to produce the sperm
for the “men”), then in this world the new sex we are imagining, which looks
identical to the female sex but which we are calling “men”, would not make
restrictive abortion laws.”
The main problem with this
analysis, however, is that the best theory for the origin of patriarchy puts
uteruses – the nature of female reproduction – front and centre, meaning that
it is almost certainly not reasonable to imagine a world in which
uterus-holders are the sex oppressing the other. The dominant theory for the
origin of patriarchy (more precisely, the dominant theory for the fact that every
civilisation ever is a patriarchy) holds that patriarchy begins when people settle
down in chiefdoms or states. In chiefdoms or states, the wide kin connections
and strong extended-family relations of hunter-gatherer societies fall apart
(replaced by more ‘nuclear’ relations), and women no longer spend their time in
the company of other women, with a communally decided group of different possible
sexual partners (based roughly on genetic distance). Instead, women become
extremely important to their (struggling, farm-working) fathers for their
reproductive capacity – for their role as dowry generators. In order that “buyers”
of women can be assured that their family line is secure (and because males are
evolutionarily programmed to want only their sperm to enter women in whom they
have sexual interest), virginity suddenly becomes extremely important, and in
order to guarantee virginity, the veil emerges and women are kept to the home.
And thus, women become chattel.
Anyway, that was incredibly
perfunctory, but the point is that the uterus was very likely key to the origin
of patriarchy, which means, in turn, that “Men with uteruses” would not be men;
they would be women in every possible sense, including in the sense that they
would be the oppressed sex.
Finally, as for the "my body, my
right" line (or the emphasis on “bodily autonomy” in general), it should
be obvious why this isn’t a trump card: it presupposes that there is nothing
wrong with abortion. Rapists aren't allowed to defend themselves by saying
"my body, my right" – and why? Because one's bodily autonomy ends
when it affects another's.
Now, there is, of course, a
perfectly respectable way of arguing that there is nothing wrong with abortion
(any instance of abortion, no matter what trimester the woman is in, no matter
her personal circumstances and the effects a baby would have on her life), and
this is the Singerian way. However, as we will later see, it does have
implications that most find very
unsavoury and deeply unsettling. Meanwhile, Don Marquis’ argument that
abortion is seriously wrong (that individual abortions may be more or less
wrong (depending on woman’s circumstance, etc) but that all abortions are
probably more wrong than, say, any case of theft) has its own very troubling
implications – primarily for population ethics. The fact that both these
positions are unsatisfactory in their own way will ultimately lead me to a very
odd conclusion. But we’ll get to that much later.
Because Don Marquis and Peter
Singer both employ the same style of moral reasoning (the only possible style
of moral reasoning, which essentially involves figuring out which moral
position on the given contentious moral issue is most compatible with moral
principles that people would overwhelmingly agree on), it is not surprising
that they have a lot of common ground. Both Marquis and Singer agree that lots
of ‘factors’ make individual acts of killing wrong, and that the differing
presence of these factors in different cases explains why not all acts of killing are equally wrong
(killing Hitler is less wrong than killing Gandhi, etc). Both also use the word
“killing” in such a way that entails that aborting a foetus is an act of
killing (so there is no semantic gulf). Finally, both think there is a feature
of a sizeable subset of acts of killing whose presence in a given act of
killing is sufficient to make that act
of killing wrong, irrespective of other
factors. For Marquis, the key feature is deprivation of conscious, intelligent experience: he claims that
the effect that the killing of humans (or proto-humans) who have a possible,
conscious future has in depriving these creatures of future prospects – of
future experience, of future joy, love and fulfilment, of future goals and
achievements – is that feature of a sizeable subset of acts of killing whose
presence is sufficient to make any
act of killing with that feature wrong (incidentally, this principle may ‘justify’
the common belief that killing animals (other species) with a future is not
necessarily seriously wrong: even other mammals probably don’t have the same
richness of experience as humans, or the same ability to remember the past and
to formulate long-term goals for the future, which means the deprivation is not
as great). For Singer, the feature of a sizeable subset of acts of killing
whose presence in a given act of killing is sufficient
to make that act of killing wrong is the effect that that the killing of
creatures with an ‘ideal desire to live’ has
in denying these creatures their life. So whereas Marquis emphasises the
importance of objective deprivation, Singer thinks what matters more is the victim’s
psychology.
At this point, you may be
wondering what work the “ideal” adjective does in Singer’s story. The
answer is not actually straightforward. The obvious work it’s doing is covering
every case where the person killed has a ‘good life’ and is more or less ‘content’
but who feels no specific desire at the point of their being killed to “live”
(including cases where the person killed is asleep or temporarily unconscious
and thus probably has no ‘desires’ at all (depending on one’s understanding of
philosophy of desire)). I think Singer has also suggested that it may cover
cases where the person killed is depressed and feels terrible about life and
their future, but would, if they had not been killed, soon overcome their
depression. However, this does seem a little dodgy (does it not?).
Marquis, meanwhile, thinks that –
regardless of other factors – it is wrong to kill a person who is severely
depressed and will never emerge from their depression, unless their depression
is so bad that they won’t even have any
future worth living. Singer would have to say, I believe, that killing a
severely depressed person who will never emerge from their depression is not
necessarily wrong, even if they do actually have some future worth living (the
killing may, of course, be wrong because of the distress it will cause other
people (family members, friends, etc)).
The above implication of Singer’s
position is, I suspect, already a little bit troubling to some people, but that’s
not half of it. There are actually far more troubling implications – and these
implications are the reason for the controversy Singer has often faced (in
particular, the massive backlash to Singer in Germany). It’s obvious why
placing the emphasis on the ‘ideal desire to live’ makes abortion permissible,
because there is no reason to think that foetuses are capable of having a “desire
to live”, or probably even anything we could reasonably call a “desire” at all
(and having an unwanted baby can, of course, ruin women’s lives, as well as the
lives of those around her). But placing the emphasis on the ‘ideal desire to
live’ also means that killing the mentally disabled, killing senile and
impaired old people, and killing very small infants (at least), is not wrong in itself. That is to say, if
killing a mentally disabled child wouldn’t cause anyone distress and if the
killing was carried out in such a way that didn’t cause the mentally disabled
child any suffering, then Singer believes it would be permissible. Even if it
did cause his mother a nontrivial degree of distress, it would only be wrong in
proportion to that amount of distress. I think many people find this to be a
repugnant conclusion.[1]
I have myself invented a thought
experiment where our intuitions seem to strongly militate against the Singerian
position (the thought experiment was originally contained in the aforementioned
essay called “Deep Moral Dilemmas and the Futility of Formalisation”):
"Imagine, if you will, a healthy woman late in the first trimester of her pregnancy, roughly 10-12 weeks in (the start of foetushood). Suppose, if you can, that one day this woman contracts a very strange and disturbing urge. For whatever reason – be it insanity, iniquity or both – there is nothing in the world she wants more to do than scramble her foetus’ brains. We can also suppose she has three methods at her disposal. She could hire an unscrupulous and highly skilled surgeon who could use keyhole surgery to get inside the uterus, break through the weak skull and fiddle around carefully with the developing brain; she could ingest some kind of futuristic nanotechnology capsule which heads directly towards the uterus and, when on a conduit towards it, begins to release some kind of neurotoxic chemical; or she could just drink a lot of alcohol and take a lot of harmful drugs. Since her desire is not wanton malice, it is important to her that she does not do so much damage that the foetus dies. Indeed, she does want the foetus to survive to become a braindamaged baby and human. Thus, whichever method this woman opts for, we can be sure she will be careful not to take it too far."
"Imagine, if you will, a healthy woman late in the first trimester of her pregnancy, roughly 10-12 weeks in (the start of foetushood). Suppose, if you can, that one day this woman contracts a very strange and disturbing urge. For whatever reason – be it insanity, iniquity or both – there is nothing in the world she wants more to do than scramble her foetus’ brains. We can also suppose she has three methods at her disposal. She could hire an unscrupulous and highly skilled surgeon who could use keyhole surgery to get inside the uterus, break through the weak skull and fiddle around carefully with the developing brain; she could ingest some kind of futuristic nanotechnology capsule which heads directly towards the uterus and, when on a conduit towards it, begins to release some kind of neurotoxic chemical; or she could just drink a lot of alcohol and take a lot of harmful drugs. Since her desire is not wanton malice, it is important to her that she does not do so much damage that the foetus dies. Indeed, she does want the foetus to survive to become a braindamaged baby and human. Thus, whichever method this woman opts for, we can be sure she will be careful not to take it too far."
We thus imagine that this woman
brings a severely retarded child into the world, probably blind and
unco-ordinated and maybe with autonomic issues, and that it’s all her fault. The
terrifying thing is that Singer’s position entails that there is absolutely
nothing wrong with this, except insofar as it causes other people distress – and
it may not cause anyone distress. In fact, if we imagine that the woman kills
the retarded child soon after it is born, without anyone’s knowledge (and
painlessly), then Singer would say that nothing bad has happened at all. In
fact, if she is such a sadist that this whole sick performance gives her
pleasure, then Singer would be forced to the conclusion that this series of
events is overall a good thing.
My friend HR tried to get around
this thought experiment by means of the following argument:
"The scrambling is wrong at the moment of its occurrence for the same reason that my setting up on the footpath a caltrop which contains a neurotoxin that will seriously retard the first person to step on the caltrop is wrong at the moment of its occurrence: it drastically increases the probability that a misfortune will befall an unconsenting agent.
"The scrambling is wrong at the moment of its occurrence for the same reason that my setting up on the footpath a caltrop which contains a neurotoxin that will seriously retard the first person to step on the caltrop is wrong at the moment of its occurrence: it drastically increases the probability that a misfortune will befall an unconsenting agent.
That the infant is born retarded
– was never a non-retarded person, as the caltrop victim was – is immaterial:
what matters is that the infant is indeed a person at the moment of its birth
and thenceforth. It is when the infant becomes a person (whenever we judge that
to be) that a victim of the mother comes into existence. (Whether the person
retarded by their mother is eventually capable of comprehending their plight,
or wishing it were otherwise, is also irrelevant: it is sufficient that all
people considered sound of mind [like the caltrop victim] would consider mental
soundness preferable to mental deficiency [and it is this preference that
generates the initial intuition that the scrambler is acting immorally {and
even if one took the ignorance-is-bliss line, in favour of retardation, the
mother remains condemnable for acting in a way /she/ believes to be harming an eventual
person}]).
This is a structural similarity
between two cases that evinces the importance of victimisability in ethical
problems.
But what if the caltrop contained
not a retardant but a fatal neurotoxin? It is indisputable that the act is
still deeply immoral – for it is a form of unjustified murder, an axiomatic sin
in the world’s ethical systems. Is abortion, the antenatal analogue,
equivalently immoral? No, and this is the kicker: because there never exists a
person to be the victim of an act of killing. In the scrambling case, a person
comes to suffer a misfortune initiated before their personhood. In the
retardant caltrop case, a person comes to sustain an ill in the ‘normal’ way
that people sustain ills – so too in the case of the fatal caltrop. But in the
case of abortion, no person is /deprived/, to use Marquis’ buzzword, of a
valuable future. There is no person. A future in which a foetus becomes a
person is merely averted.
Your fatal error in interpreting
your own thought experiment was to focus to the exclusion of all else on the
fact of a particular future being averted in both the case of the scrambling (a
future in which there exists a mentally sound person) and the abortion (a
future in which a person exists). You treated this similarity as one that
renders the two cases equivalent, but they’re not. You assumed that we impute
wrongness to the scrambling /only/ because it involves the aversion of a
preferable future, but this is incorrect. The scrambling is wrong because the
preferable future of a /particular person/ is averted. You ignored the ontic
criterion."
Now this is an interesting way of
arguing (Singer plus an extra subtlety) but it's flawed, as HR conceded: the
notion that what really matters is that everyone can 'see' a victim is just an
ad hoc rationalisation of his intuitions, without basis in any familiar ethical
principle. If the human being that resulted from the disturbed woman's
pregnancy was severely retarded, and thus had no ability to conceive of himself
as a victim and feel loss, and yet we still think that what she did was wrong,
that can only be because the Marquisian objective notion of deprivation
matters, not just the Singerian deprivation+ideal desire to live.
Our intuitions about premature babies
also seem to clash with the Singerian position. If a late-second-trimester baby
is put in an infant incubator, I think 99% of people would say that it would be
deeply wrong for a nurse (or someone else) to switch off the machine and allow
it to die, even if the parents never found out that the baby had been killed
and therefore never had to feel the distress of knowing that someone had
intervened in their baby’s future.
Of course, the Marquisian
position that abortion is seriously wrong (not as bad as murdering a human
being out of the womb who has loved ones and specific goals, but still very
wrong) and should be avoided if at all possible has some of its own problems.
As we’ve seen, Marquis' big claim is that objective deprivation of future
experience is what matters. Marquis claims to surmount the regress objection – 'But
doesn't your view make wanking wrong?' – by putting the morally significant
boundary at the point of clear individuation. The problem with putting the
significant boundary at the point of clear individuation (which Marquis has
suggested is after the 16-cell stage, when the cells are no longer 'totipotent'
and no 'twinning' can occur) is that we can now split these totipotent cells
and implant them into women to gestate. It seems that Marquis would say that
all these humans in potentia should be born, or at least preserved for as long
as possible – and this does seem to raise big problems for population ethics.
And it might be worse than this: it’s not clear that he wouldn’t be forced to
the conclusion that we should split
the totipotent cells. Marquis would almost certainly reject this claim, and he
would defend this rejection by saying that the fact that it’s bad to destroy
any one of the post-split cells does not imply that it is good to create more potential life by splitting the totipotent
cells to begin with. But I’m not sure of this response: I think it’s ultimately
not clear why, if depriving life is such a terrible thing, it’s in no way a
good thing to try to create more of it. How can life and conscious experience
be simultaneously so valuable that losing the potential for any is a great
tragedy, and so unimportant that it is not in any way actually a good thing to
create more?
In general, if you look at the
bigger picture – all the larger issues tangled up in the actual practical
reality of abortion – Marquis’ position does seem, even if ‘right’, not ‘implementable’
in an ethical way. It would be natural to suppose that someone who feels that
abortions are seriously morally wrong would want to stop women having abortions
post-haste. However, the fact is that if just a small percentage of women
around the world with unwanted pregnancies decided to forego an abortion
because of government policy instituted as a result of this moral conclusion, that
would lead to a massive jump in population
(and would continue to have an effect on increasing the population if women were
(somehow) continuously made to maintain unwanted pregnancies). This, in turn,
would, of course, lead to the further degradation of the planet, further claims
over limited resources, further poverty, further urban overcrowding, and
exacerbate the terrifying, possibly existential (to civilisation) ecological
disaster we are already facing.
Pro-choicers often make a similar
point, though with a focus on how punitive laws affect female happiness and
feminism rather than on ecology and society as a whole. They point out that
banning abortion at clinics is certainly not going to eliminate all abortions –
it may not even significantly reduce the overall rate of abortions – and
probably leads to more misery in the world by forcing women into parlous
situations or forcing them to have children which they do not want, at risk to
their dreams and careers.
Marquis would probably claim
that, because he can recognise the very bad things that would result from punitive
law changes on abortion, he doesn’t really believe that it would be desirable
to stop all women having abortions, unless this outcome was achieved by birth control. But whilst this would be
a good response to this particular objection, this retreat might induce us to
question whether he really thinks abortion is seriously wrong.
Of course, Singer, like any
utilitarian, does himself have to deal with more theoretical issues in population
ethics – those raised by Derek Parfit in Reasons
and Persons. But clearly by having a permissive view of abortion, he avoids
all of Marquis’ problems.
So, seeing as both positions face
problems, what’s my conclusion? The answer is that I think the abortion debate
reveals the limits of ethical reasoning. I think there's no clear fact of the
matter; I think that abortions perhaps should be avoided (even first-trimester
abortions), but I really don’t strong feelings about this (especially because
it’s easier to empathise with the woman who already exists than the
proto-person). That’s my strange view.
And so why do I support lenient
abortion laws? Precisely because I don’t really have strong feelings about the ethics
of abortion. The government shouldn’t legally prevent women from doing
something that is not unambiguously seriously wrong (which is why even Marquis’
position doesn’t necessarily have
strong legislative implications, as we just saw).
[1] To
be fair, Marquis’ position itself suggests that killing a mentally disabled
person may be less bad, all else being equal, than killing someone of high
intelligence, because there is probably less to deprive.
No comments:
Post a Comment