Search This Blog

Tuesday 28 June 2016

Some Good, Old-fashioned Epistemology: Three Essays on Knowing

(2) Discuss the following claim.  Is it true or false, and why?
‘Even scepticism is right, and we lack much of the knowledge we ordinary take ourselves to have, it’s not too worrying.  We can acknowledge that scepticism is right but then just go on with our lives as before.’

I would say this claim about scepticism is absolutely true, if by scepticism we mean Cartesian external world scepticism and Humean inductivist scepticism (i.e. the forms of scepticism practised in philosophy classrooms). The reasons are, to me, pretty obvious. If one is too worried about Cartesian scepticism about the external world then one is liable to be diagnosed with psychosis and Solipsism Syndrome – so clearly, it is not sage advice to let that most extreme form of scepticism overtake one’s mind. One has no option but to go on with life as before, even if one thinks that scepticism about the external world is strictly speaking irrefutable (as I do). David Hume’s scepticism about induction and the reality of causation is arguably a good reminder of the inherent fragility of human knowledge, but it is of no use in any other way: no human has the ability to take scepticism about induction seriously outside the philosophy classroom, and if you tried to frequently remind yourself of the strength of Hume’s argument, that would presumably either drive you insane or perhaps make you a total relativist (which, I will argue, is stupid in its own way). So yes, we can indeed acknowledge that scepticism is right and then just go on with our lives as before.

At the start of his Meditations on First Philosophy, Rene Descartes describes (in the present-tense) his decision to embark upon a process of “doubting”. Very soon, this practice of “methodical doubt” leads him to rather disturbing conclusions. The first of these is that he might be in a dream. As he writes, since “on many occasions [he has] in sleep been deceived” by exactly the “illusions” he sees in front of him, he cannot know that he is not sleeping at that very moment (Descartes, 1641, p. 1-7). While this thought is (of course) extremely disquieting, there is a small consolation: even if the doubt is justified, he is “bound to confess that there are at least some other objects yet more simple and more universal [than those he sees in either the dreams or ‘real-life’], which are real and true” (Descartes, p. 1-7).[1] However, after some more meditation, he suddenly recognises that all of reality might be illusory. His new thought is that he could be under the control of an evil demon who “has employed his whole energies in deceiving me” (Descartes, p. 1-8). If this were true, it would mean that “the heavens, the earth, colours, figures, sound, and all other external things are nought but the illusions and dreams of which this genius has availed himself in order to lay traps for my credulity” (Descartes, p. 1-8).
From “Meditations I” to “Meditations III”, Descartes does, of course, attempt to argue his way out of this extreme doubt. In “Meditation I: Concerning Those Things That Can Be Called into Doubt”, soon after imagining the evil demon, he supposedly demonstrates that the existence of the Ego is apodictic by observing that he cannot doubt that he is doubting.[2] In “Meditation III: Concerning God, That He Exists”, he uses the Ego to provide a ‘proof’ that a benevolent God must be real, and thus supposedly demonstrates that reality can’t possibly be an illusion, since a benevolent God would not give him a false picture of reality (Descartes, p. 1-13 to 1-19).
Unfortunately for Descartes, to modern sensibilities, these arguments are deeply unsatisfactory. At the same time, no strong arguments have been proposed to replace them. The end-result is that few contemporary philosophers think that one can declare the evil demon supposition truly impossible (even if they dismiss the dream thought experiment).
One might think that a philosopher could respond to this doubt by simply “lowering her credence function” in the external world (or some other such stupid thing), and that Cartesian scepticism could therefore be ‘implemented’ in real life to some degree. However, the problem with even conceding the possibility that nothing is real except one’s own mind is that that itself has rather paradoxical implications. If we imagine that all of reality is an illusion created by an evil demon, it follows, for example, that Descartes and his Meditations must be an illusion too, as must all of philosophy, and philosophers, and the arguments of philosophers, and discourse in general. Just as bizarrely, since this kind of Cartesian doubt is fundamentally subjectivist, each philosopher ought really to be addressing the question using the first-person – saying it is possible that “I am being deceived by an evil demon”, rather than “Descartes shows that it is possible that all of reality is an illusion except our minds”. And yet, if you do address the question using the first-person, then there’s no point even having a conversation about Cartesian scepticism with other philosophers. I know that I can’t know for sure that these other philosophers exist, and maybe they are having the exact same thought, but I can’t know that they even exist. It is easy to see why it would be psychologically unhealthy to spend too much time worrying about this in real life.  
It’s notable that Descartes never imagines that the evil demon has tampered with the laws of logic themselves (he doesn’t doubt modus pomens, for example). The reasons for this are, of course, obvious – though not uninteresting, since I think they point to the ultimate futility of extreme scepticism.
The modern update of the evil-demon thought experiment is the famous “Brain in a Vat” thought experiment, and this – as far as I can tell – has exactly the same implications, and is precisely as difficult to refute.[3] It is also precisely as irrelevant to real life.

David Hume’s scepticism about induction and causation seems, on the face of it, to be rather different from the extreme doubt of Descartes. Instead of doubting everything, Hume argues that one method of knowing we normally take for granted – inductive reasoning – is actually not nearly so secure as it seems. One might almost be tempted to say that this is something that we could take seriously in our lives. However, as I will argue, I don’t think this is so.  
The extreme Locke-influenced empiricism of Hume’s approach even led him to proclaim that not even the relation of “cause and effect” is necessary. As he wrote, “the knowledge of this relation is not, in any instance, attained by reasonings a priori; but arises entirely from experience, when we find that any particular objects are constantly conjoined with each other” (Hume, Section IV, Part I). To Hume, this meant it was highly doubtful.
In order to defeat Hume’s scepticism about induction, one does, of course, need only one assumption: that nature is uniform. Modern scientists would say that this assumption is clearly correct, given that – ever since Newton – the physics profession has been able to come up with laws that capture a deep reality with profound stability (allowing one to make all sorts of novel predictions, like – recently – the existence of gravitational waves). But Hume was himself writing after Newton, and clearly didn’t think his law of universal gravitation falsified his point. Hume would have claimed that, despite the explanatory and predictive successes of Newton’s equations, there is still no way of knowing that when you wake up tomorrow you won’t float to the ceiling of your room (and apples won’t fly up when you “drop” them), because there is no law guaranteeing that physical laws are fixed. No doubt all physicists would dispute this – but that is only because they are assuming that the laws of nature couldn’t themselves suddenly change (despite this being clearly logically possible).
 Much as it is with Descartes, I certainly think that Hume achieved an important philosophical milestone by adopting this sceptical attitude towards a way of reasoning we take for granted every day. Much as it is with Descartes, I think he’s right that no inductive reasoning is ever absolutely certain in the way that we can be absolutely certain that 2 and 2 makes 4. One difference with Cartesian scepticism is, I think, that there is possibly one way of at least half-solving Hume’s scepticism which doesn’t involve saying, “Oh well, I must get on with my life”. This half-solution is to suggest that it’s just a basic conceptual mistake to hold inductive reasoning to the standards of deductive reasoning. Can we not say that inductive and deductive reasoning are just two different kinds of reasoning, and that both of them ought to be judged on their own terms?
In any case, even though it is perfectly true that inductive reasoning is only justifiable by begging the question (“It’s worked in the past!”), it is not as if deductive reasoning can justify itself either – except by appeal to our most basic intuitions (“If A, then ¬¬A”)). Justifying justification is evidently always quite a task.
Another nuance of scepticism about induction that distinguishes it from Cartesian external world scepticism is that it seems like it cannot be an all-or-nothing thing (despite the impression Hume presents). Indeed, one problem with Hume’s writings on induction is that he fails to mention the feature of induction that a “frequentist” would immediately point out: that some outcomes are simply more probable than others, and that this truth remains even if you doubt that any inductive reasoning is absolutely certain. One clearly doesn’t need Hume to be highly sceptical of poorly founded inductive inferences like “My child seemed to develop autism after a vaccination, therefore vaccines cause autism”, and yet one can clearly also have very high confidence in any inductive claim that is based on well-tested scientific theories and mountains of evidence (“Human beings and Neanderthals both evolved from a species of hominid that we call Homo heidelbergensis”, “The universe is approximately 13.7 billion years old”, “Human beings are warming the climate”, etc). It certainly seems to make zero sense to say, “Hume is right, therefore all inductive reasoning is unreliable”. Instead, if one accepts the Humean position, one is forced to think of things on different levels of epistemology. The right way of thinking about Hume seems to be to acknowledge that inductive reasoning is never absolutely certain, but also that some kinds of inductive reasoning are extremely close to absolutely certain and that other kinds are extremely far from absolutely certain.
Hume’s own ‘solution’ to this extreme scepticism was, of course, to ignore it except when he was writing his books. In Section V of An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, called “A Sceptical Solution of these Doubts”, Hume says the following: “Nor need we fear that this philosophy, while it endeavours to limit our enquiries to common life, should ever undermine the reasonings of common life, and carry its doubts so far as to destroy all action, as well as speculation. Nature will always maintain her rights, and prevail in the end over any abstract reasoning whatsoever” (Hume, Section V, Part I). This captures the idea that it is just not in human nature to avoid believing in the reliability of such fundamental reasoning. Near the end of Book I of A Treatise of Human Nature – his first work, where he first explored this kind of scepticism – he describes himself undergoing a kind of existential breakdown in response to the terrifying implications of his results, but then remarks, “Most fortunately it happens, that since reason is incapable of dispelling these clouds, nature herself suffices to that purpose, and cures me of this philosophical melancholy and delirium, either by relaxing this bent of mind, or by some avocation, and lively impression of my senses, which obliterate all these chimeras. I dine, I play a game of back-gammon, I converse, and am merry with my friends; and when after three or four hours' amusement, I wou'd return to these speculations, they appear so cold, and strain'd, and ridiculous, that I cannot find in my heart to enter into them any farther” (Hume, 1737, p. 269).  
To me, this passage sums up how we should – and usually do – respond to scepticism: namely, by treating it as an intellectual exercise that has no relevance to real life at all (except, perhaps, when demonstrating the fascination of philosophy to non-philosophers).


Bibliography

Descartes, R. 1641, Meditations on First Philosophy, in The Philosophical Works of Descartes (1911), trans. Elizabeth Haldane, Cambridge University Press.

Hedden, B. Lecture notes.

Hume, D. 1737, A Treatise of Human Nature, 1992 edition, Prometheus Books, New York.

Hume, D. 1741, An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, 1910 edition, Harvard Classics. Accessed from:
<http://18th.eserver.org/hume-enquiry.html#5>     


1.) Suppose that you and your friend (who you take to be just as rational as you) examine some evidence about what killed the dinosaurs. You decide it’s 90% likely that the cause was a meteorite, while your friend says he thinks it’s only 50% likely that the cause was a meteorite. (i) Does your disagreement mean that one of you was less than perfectly rational in evaluating the evidence? And (ii) what should you do once you learn of your disagreement with your friend (should you drop your confidence that the cause was a meteorite)? Does what you say about (i) affect what you should say about (ii)?

On simple questions of fact or probability, it is perfectly obvious that “uniquism” is the correct thesis about epistemic consensus (ignoring issues of classic philosophical scepticism). That is, if two fully rational agents are evaluating such questions with the same body of evidence (and the amount of evidence is adequate to reach a verdict) they will necessarily reach the same verdict. Nonetheless, as Thomas Kelly argues in the paper “Evidence can be Permissive” (2014), the clash between uniquism and “permissivism” (the position that there are at least some questions or debates on which fully rational agents can develop different doxastic attitudes towards the same body of evidence) becomes a great deal trickier when the cases themselves become more complex. Though a uniquist would, of course, want to put this down to human failures, there is also a substantive epistemological reason why disagreements necessarily become less clear-cut (less obviously a product of one-sided irrationality) in empirical cases of great complexity. This reason is that the role of seemingly non-objective epistemic standards must grow greater as the relevant hypotheses or theories are increasingly underdetermined by the available evidence.
The case given by this question is evidently an empirical case of considerable complexity – one on which expert scientists do in fact disagree in real life – and one in which epistemic standards of theoretical simplicity and ‘Jamesian trade-offs’ would, I believe, be crucial. At the same time, I am not sure that an ideally rational agent mightn’t be able to work out, by means of some highly sophisticated philosophy of science, what are objectively (or at least “intersubjectively”) the best epistemic standards to apply to the development of hypotheses for the extinction of the dinosaurs. Thus, if I am to interpret the phrase “perfectly rational” in the question as meaning “ideally rational”, I am simply agnostic about whether a disagreement of credence of this type (90% probability versus 50% probability for the meteor hypothesis) could exist between two ideally rational agents. However, I certainly believe that, if one takes a weaker, more ‘human’ sense of rational (meaning “reasonable, clear-eyed, rigorous”), then the permissivist perspective is likely correct here: I don’t think a disagreement of this degree on such a difficult question as the causation of an event that happened 66 million years ago would (in itself) be enough conclude that one of us must be less than rational. As for how I should react to learning of the difference in probability assignments between me and my friend, my answer would be simply, It depends. Like Jennifer Lackey, I don’t subscribe either to “conformism” or “non-conformism” as absolute doctrines on how to resolve disagreement, and believe instead that specific details matter. In this case, the relevant details would be the opinions of the experts in the field, and various facts about the different ways in which my friend and I evaluated the evidence. Overall, I think the answers to both questions (our rationality in this situation, and how we should resolve our disagreement) aren’t straightforward, and can’t be answered in abstract, purely philosophical terms.

The question of what killed the dinosaurs is clearly not an easy one to answer. To understand the series of events that caused the mass extinction that took place on our planet 66 million years ago, one has to successfully look into the ancient past and successfully evaluate the unfolding of that past, all on the basis of some highly fragmentary, degenerate evidence from geology and archaeology. The magnitude of this challenge becomes clearer when one reflects on how difficult it is for us to understand the dynamics of our planetary system today. For example, in order to assess the claim that human activity is warming the climate, we currently feed mountains of data into state-of-the-art mathematical models and, even then, projections as to future warming and sea-level rises vary widely from expert to expert (despite these experts’ nominal status as “epistemic peers”). Given these facts, it is not at all surprising that there is also fairly wide expert disagreement in real life over what “killed the dinosaurs” – probably more so than there is over the effect of humans on the climate. There is, of course, a consensus that c. 66 million years ago, in a very short space of geological time, a mass extinction event or series of events took place, and that a meteor strike or strikes had (at the very least) something to do with this cataclysm (“Cretaceous–Paleogene extinction event”, Wikipedia, 24 June 2016). But there is no consensus about most of the other details of the event or events: with regard to the meteor hypothesis, there is dispute between the original single-impact “Alvarrez hypothesis” (focussing on Mexico’s Chicxulub crater) and the more recent “Multiple impact hypothesis”; there is controversy over the importance of the “Deccan traps” in polluting the atmosphere, and over the mechanisms by which it could have had this effect; and there is controversy between those who opt for the “multiple causes” thesis, with a longer time-frame of extinction, and those who insist on one sudden, catastrophic cause (usually the meteor strike) (“Cretaceous–Paleogene extinction event”, Wikipedia, 24 June 2016).
Early in his paper “Evidence can be Permissive”, Thomas Kelly makes an important, if obvious, point about how cases of this complexity affect the debate between permissivism and uniquism. He points out that, if “uniquism” is right, it has to be a fairly flexible thesis, since it can’t possibly be saying the same thing for simple cases and for more complicated cases (like that of the dinosaur-extinction) (Kelly, 2014: 2). Kelly uses the example of a moderate disagreement over the future outcome of a US Presidential election to argue that there’s an inherent fuzziness to disagreements over complex cases. Kelly makes this argument by means of a thought experiment: he imagines that the standard doxastic attitudes of Alpha Centaurians towards such future events are, unlike our own doxastic attitudes, always ultra fine-grained – for example, “believing to degree .5436497 that the Democrat will win, or believing to degree .5122894 that it will rain tomorrow” (Kelly, 2014: 3). As he observes, it would seem highly counterintuitive if uniquism were true about doxastic attitudes as fine-grained as those. Importantly, since this thought experiment shows that there must be some limit to the stringency of a fully rational doxastic attitude, it suddenly becomes much harder to deny the specific, sensibly defended parameters that Kelly allows in the Presidential-prediction case.
In my view, the same kind of partial reductio would apply in the case of disagreement over dinosaur-extinction. Clearly, it cannot be the case that the only ideally rational attitude towards the hypothesis that the meteor strike killed the dinosaurs is a probability assignment with several decimal points.  But, of course, just as it did with Kelly, the major question still remains: just how narrow is the allowable range of probability assessments? In my view, the answer has to do with epistemic standards.
Fortunately, Kelly himself deals with exactly this issue of epistemic standards. After finishing the Presidential-prediction example, Kelly introduces a relevant idea from William James, the father of both psychology and Pragmatism: that reaching the ‘correct answer’ is not so simple a matter as “attaining truth and avoiding error”, but involves an inherent trade-off between two opposing goals – “not believing what is false”, and “believing what is true” (Kelly, 2014: 6). While someone targeting the former goal (an ‘intellectual conservative’) will be inclined to suspend judgment at the slightest doubt,[1] someone targeting the latter (an ‘intellectual risk-taker’) will be willing to place much more confidence in the hypothesis they think is true, even if there is not yet overwhelming evidence for it. Kelly argues that both these epistemic strategies, in moderate forms, are perfectly rational and acceptable, which gives an obvious support for a permissive view (Kelly, 2014: 8). I agree with this claim of Kelly’s, and I believe it has direct implications for our case. If we imagine, for example, that I am the intellectual risk-taker in the situation, this gives us some clue as to how I might have diverged from my friend while still remaining as rational as her. Perhaps I regarded the hypothesis that the dinosaurs were wiped out by a single meteor strike to be simple, parsimonious and emotionally satisfying (aesthetic epistemic standards), and when I discovered that significant evidence supports it, this lifted its standing well beyond the other hypotheses. Meanwhile, perhaps my friend decided that she was going to do her best to evaluate the evidence on its own merits, and when that process was concluded, she just didn’t think there was enough to be very confident about any hypothesis over any other.
As I suggested in the introduction, I don’t really know if an ideally rational agent would be an intellectual risk-taker in the dinosaur-extinction case or an intellectual conservative. I’m not really sure of the epistemic status of epistemic standards in general – to what extent the valuation of “simplicity” (or the use of “Occam’s Razor”) represents an objective principle, and whether there are anything like objective truths as to how much of an intellectual risk-taker one should be. I think it possible that an ideally rational agent might just have some highly sophisticated philosophy of science that would allow her to decide in a given case whether she should take an intellectual risk or be an intellectual conservative – but I don’t really know. All in all, therefore, I would prefer to remain agnostic on the question of whether either I or my friend is necessarily being less than ideally rational in this case.
As I also suggested in the introduction, however, I think on a more down-to-earth conception of rationality, there is little reason to think that our gap in probability assignments on such a difficult question would necessarily make one of us irrational. As I’ve already made clear, I do think it’s possible at least to conceive of a scenario in which we both reached very different probability assignments on the hypothesis of the meteor strike simply because of different Jamesian trade-offs (without either of us being too extreme in either our risk-taking or intellectual conservatism). So, while in real life, I’m sure I would be very tempted to call my friend “irrational” if I found out she had such a significant disagreement with me (and would probably assume that she didn’t pay enough attention to this or that bit of evidence), it seems to me that from a third-person perspective, we could still both be rational with such a disagreement (especially given the complexity of the case).
On the question of how to deal with a disagreement of this kind, I opt for the “Justificationist” position espoused by Jennifer Lackey in her paper “What’s the rational response to everyday disagreement?”[2]. In short, I believe that there is no absolute, invariant answer as to how we should deal with disagreements among epistemic peers, and that instead, context-dependent considerations are all important. In the dinosaur-extinction case, it’s not hard to think of what might be counted as relevant considerations. If I was directly aware of a key piece of evidence my friend had overlooked somewhat (without her being irrational per se), then I’d be less inclined to adjust my credence to match, but (conversely), if I was aware that I’d lacked the expertise to understand something that she did understand, I would think it clearly rational to adjust my credence by some degree. Similarly, if I was aware that my position was the one held by the majority of the experts in the field, then I would not feel inclined to adjust my credence at all (and vice versa).[3]
To answer the last sub-question of the question: yes, my response to the question of me and my friend’s rationality has affected what I said about how I should react to my disagreement. If I had concluded that the disagreement would necessarily make one of us irrational, my Justificationism would have led me to a more directly conformist view in this case; I would have said that both me and my friend should look for errors we might have made in our evaluation of the evidence, and that we should both come closer in probability assignments until such time as we find evidence that one party made bigger mistakes than the other.

In summary, I think the following about the disagreement of me and my friend over the extinction of the dinosaurs: in response to i.) given the complexity of the dinosaur-extinction case and the significance of epistemic standards, I don’t know for sure if either I or my friend would necessarily be less than fully rational, but I think it is clear that this level of disagreement in itself isn’t enough to make either of us irrational in a conventional sense; in response to ii.) I think that there is no absolute answer as to what I should do upon learning of this disagreement (it depends); and in response to the last sub-question, my answer is yes, because I am a Justificationist about disagreement.

Very Brief Reference List:

Hedden, Brian. Lecture notes.

Kelly, Thomas (2014). “Evidence can be Permissive”, in Steup, Turri and Sosa (eds.) Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, Wiley-Blackwell: 298-311.

Lackey, Jennifer (2012). “What’s the rational response to everyday disagreements?”, in The Philosopher’s Magazine, 4th Quarter: 101-106.  

“Cretaceous-Paleogene Extinction Event” (well-cited), Wikipedia, last updated 24 June 2016. Accessed 25 June 2016:
<https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Cretaceous%E2%80%93Paleogene_extinction_event>
                                                                                    
(3) The claim Positive Introspection says that if you know that P, then you are in a position to know that you know P. The claim Negative Introspection says that if you don’t know that P, then you are in a position to know that you don’t know P. Are either or both of these claims true? Evaluate them using theories of knowledge covered in the course, such as those of Descartes, Nozick, and Goldman

I believe the claim “Positive Introspection” is true for our most certain knowledge but can be denied otherwise. I believe the claim “Negative Introspection” is completely false. Unlike most of the philosophers who have attempted to circumscribe how much we can really know (eg Descartes), or analyse ‘knowledge’ (eg Gettier, Nozick or Goldman), I don’t think it makes much sense to treat knowledge as one monolith. Instead, I think we ought to use the principle of Positive Introspection to distinguish three types of knowledge: 1.) absolute, Cartesian knowledge, which requires us not only to be in a position to know that we know, but in a position to know that we know for sure; 2.) certain, non-Cartesian knowledge, which requires only the standard principle of Positive Introspection; and 3.) weak or incidental knowledge, which is justified true belief that we are not in a position to know that we know. The only absolute Cartesian knowledge is that one’s thoughts exist, because that is the only thing that one is in a position to know that one knows for sure (that one can’t rationally doubt). Certain non-Cartesian knowledge is all accessibilist internalist justified true belief (justified true belief for which you can access some adequate justification). Weak or incidental knowledge is all justified true belief that qualifies under externalist and mentalist internalist lights but not accessibilist internalist lights (justified true belief which you know without any adequate, accessible internal justification).
Rene Descartes was one philosopher who clearly believed in the principle of Positive Introspection and denied the principle of Negative Introspection. In The Meditations, Descartes famously begins his process of “methodical doubt” because he wants to identify wholly solid foundations for knowledge. As quickly becomes clear, Descartes believes that in order for the foundations of knowledge to be wholly solid, they need to be wholly indubitable. In Descartes’ view, if he reasons that he might be in a dream as he stares at the room in front of him, then he cannot know that he is not (Descartes, 1641: 1-7). If he reasons that he might be under the control of an evil demon “who has employed all his energies in deceiving [him]”, then he cannot know that all of external reality – “the heavens, the earth, colours, figures, sound, and all other external things” – is not just “the illusions and dreams of which this genius has availed himself in order to lay traps for my credulity” (Descartes, 1641: 1-8). Ultimately, and famously, the terminus of his methodical doubt is doubt itself, and from this bedrock (one can’t doubt that one is doubting) Descartes supposedly derives his first absolute truth: the Ego exists.[4]
I wouldn’t want to say that Descartes was necessarily wrong to conceive of knowledge in this ultra-strict way, but it is nowadays evident that his foundationalist project was doomed. I instead classify the kind of knowledge Descartes was searching for – of which there is really only one example (one’s thoughts exist) – as its own type of knowledge: absolute, Cartesian knowledge. Absolute, Cartesian knowledge requires not only that one is in a position to know that one knows P, but that one is in a position to know that one knows P for sure. Notably, when David Hume was questioning the ultimate validity of inductive reasoning and the reality of causation, he was also adopting this conception of knowledge. According to Hume, in order to know that the sun will rise tomorrow, one has to know for sure that the future is conformable to the past – but we don’t, so we don’t know that the sun will rise tomorrow. And obviously, both Descartes and Hume denied the completely false principle of Negative Introspection, since they both argued that people don’t know plenty of things that they think they do know.
As I explained in the introduction, I think there is another type of knowledge for which the principle of Positive Introspection holds: certain, non-Cartesian knowledge, which equates to accessibilist internalist justified true belief (justified true belief for which you have some adequate, accessible justification). The contemporary debate between so-called ‘internalists’ and ‘externalists’ takes back to Edmund Gettier’s hugely influential three-page paper “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?” In this short piece, Gettier imagined a few thought experiments which cleverly drew attention to the flaws in the traditional analysis of knowledge as mere “justified true belief”. As his cases with “Jones” and “Smith” showed, it is possible to have a justified true belief about some fact in a somewhat incidental fashion, in such a way that it would seem perverse to use the word “knowledge” to describe this justified true belief (it is possible to justifiably believe some fact which turns out to be the right answer, but for the wrong reason) (Gettier, 1963). Gettier’s observation spurred on fresh attempts to produce a satisfactory account of knowledge, including the Causal Theory and Reliabilist account of Alvin Goldman and the Tracking Theory of Robert Nozick. From this finally arrived the internalist/externalist debate about justification.
Internalists (best represented by the Evidentialists Richard Feldman and Earl Conee) believe that in order to know P, one must have internal, mental justification. However, it is not quite as simple as that; internalists importantly diverge on the principle of Positive Introspection. Whereas the accessibilists believe that to know P, one must have access to the justification for believing P (which directly equates to being in a position to know that one knows P), the mentalists believe that this is not necessary, only that the justification for P is somewhere in one’s mind. Accessibilist internalism is usually regarded as an untenable position, for reasons that Goldman highlights: that, any given moment, we seem to know all kinds of things (“personal facts, facts that constitute common knowledge, facts in our areas of expertise, and so on” (Conee and Feldman, 2004: 67)) which we nevertheless couldn’t really justify (Goldman, 2004). One doesn’t even need to think of a clever counterexample like Goldman’s “Sally”[5] to cast serious doubt on accessibilist internalism as a general account of knowledge, since anyone who relies on experts for information about anything (eg the origins of the universe, particle physics, chemistry, history, climate change) will have, at best, internal access only to a schematic or simplified justification for their beliefs – and yet we clearly want to say that informed laypeople can know that the universe is 13.8 billion years old, or that the earth is warming due to human activity. Even basic perceptual knowledge would be hard to justify without a good understanding of the human perceptual system (and most people do not have this).
However, I don’t believe this is at all fatal to accessibilist internalism, as long as one allows that there are two different conceptions of knowledge in question here: the accessibilist internalists are seeking an account of what I have called certain, non-Cartesian knowledge, whereas the mentalist internalists and externalists are seeking a broader account – for the mentalist internalists, it’s an account of both this kind of knowledge and “weak” knowledge, and for the externalists, it’s an account of this kind of knowledge, weak knowledge and “incidental” knowledge. In my view, the kind of knowledge which does obey the principle of Positive Introspection – the kind of knowledge for which we can access an adequate justification – is knowledge of a higher status than the knowledge for which we don’t have this kind of justification. The two kinds thus deserve to be separated.
But what do I mean by “weak” knowledge” and “incidental” knowledge? As I said in the introduction, both weak knowledge and incidental knowledge represent justified true belief for which we have no accessible justification. However, the reason I have chosen two names is that they are subtly different. By weak knowledge, I mean anything that a mentalist internalist would accept as knowledge but an accessibilist internalist would not –in other words, most everyday knowledge of things, forming part of one’s “web of belief”. On the other hand, by incidental knowledge, I mean everything that an externalist would count as knowledge but an internalist would not. According to Goldman’s “reliablist” account of knowledge (a quintessential externalist account), it doesn’t matter whether you have forgotten how to justify one of your true beliefs (and there is no justification in your head), as long as it was formed by a reliable belief-forming process (Goldman, 2004). It is this kind of knowledge, formed in the correct way, but without any internal justification, that I call “incidental”. I think the average person has a lot of incidental knowledge: things they know because they read something somewhere once, or because they heard something, or because they witnessed an incident that they can partly remember. Clearly, this knowledge doesn’t have the same status as the knowledge for which we can provide an adequate justification – but, at the same time, I think it would be a perversion of language to say that it isn’t knowledge.
In conclusion, I believe that the principle of Positive Introspection is true with respect to our most certain knowledge, and that the principle of Negative Introspection is completely false. I have laid out in this essay a pluralistic picture of knowledge, with the principle of Positive Introspection playing a crucial demarcatory role. I think absolute, Cartesian knowledge requires an extra-strong version of the principle of Positive Introspection; I think certain, non-Cartesian knowledge requires the standard version of the principle; and I think weak and incidental knowledge doesn’t require it at all.

Reference List:

Conee, Earl and Feldman, Richard (2004). Evidentialism: Essays in Epistemology, Clarendon Press, Oxford.

Descartes, Rene (1641). Meditations on First Philosophy, in The Philosophical Works of Descartes (1911), trans. Elizabeth Haldane, Cambridge University Press.

Gettier, Edmund (1963). "Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?", Analysis, 23: 121–123. 

Goldman, Alvin (2004). Pathways to Knowledge: Public and Private, Oxford University Press.

Hedden, Brian. Lecture notes.

Hume, David. 1737, A Treatise of Human Nature, 1992 edition, Prometheus Books, New York.




[1] Or perhaps maintain a ‘smeared’ probability distribution between multiple hypotheses until decisive evidence emerges.
[2] Clearly, though, I am extending its application beyond “everyday” disagreements.
[3] Deferring to the majority of experts is clearly a kind of “conformism”, but I wouldn’t necessarily recommend this kind of conformism if I was myself an expert in the extinction of the dinosaurs. So I’m not suggesting anything absolute by this.  
[4] Which is, of course, an invalid inference; one can’t go from mere thoughts to some kind of mysterious intangible entity.
[5] A woman who formed a justifiable belief about the health benefits of broccoli from a “New York Times science-section story” but later forgot her evidential source (Goldman, 2000: 10).




[1] Obviously, these “more universal” objects sound a lot like the Platonic forms.
[2] Of course, as many philosophers have pointed out, Descartes really only shows that he cannot doubt his consciousness, rather than showing that he cannot doubt the existence of a discrete entity called an Ego.  
[3] One could perhaps make the argument that the Brain in a Vat thought experiment is ever-so-slightly more possible than the Evil Demon, since at least it’s kind of “naturalistic” (it’s unclear to me whether different levels of epistemology interact here).  

Saturday 11 June 2016

A Poem called "Me, the Temporary Lumberjack"

Me, the Temporary Lumberjack

I trudge outside in the darkling Winter day,
My face resolute, hard, determined.
It is cold; I am wearing a big, black coat,
And my face is numbed and pale.

The wind is gusting as I stride down the slope
To the place where we chop our lumber.
I near the old, torn-up splittingstump,
And I reach down under the verandah.

I pull out the tool for imminent labours:
A logsplitter, massive, heavy,
Worn hard from repeated use.
Just below the blade, it's all chewed-up -
Strikes violently overshot. 

I lay the logsplitter by the old stump,
And I lift up one of the logs nearby
Forearm straining, wrist bending - breaking -
I plant it firmly on the stump.

I pick up the logsplitter again,
Gracefully, I turn it in my hand.
I enjoy its weight, its thick, hardwood heft.
I swing an arc through air to be cleft.

Now I steady myself and lift the splitter;
My hands meet at the bottom of the handle
As I reach the top of the swing... before
I pull down my weapon to strike.

CRACK.

The log splits in two jagged chunks.
Like shrapnel, each side flies off to the side.
'A perfect cut,' I think, as I stagger,
Stiff-backed, slow, to the big stack on the right.

I repeat this process with more big logs,
I do it over and over again.
Some are stubborn and knotted - I get stuck.
Some are too deformed to cut.

After two or three logs have been chopped,
My back, of course, begins throbbing.
But I keep going, relishing my strength
As I heave and hack, heave and hack, unstopped.

Minutes pass... Despite the cold, I begin to sweat.
Wood dust, wood grime are infused in my spit;
I spit in disgust, but the taste lingers.

When I stand erect after I’ve filled the barrow,
My back muscles are properly aching,
And I know it is time to stop.

I strut and stumble around my wooden midden.
The look on my face is rough-hewn and fierce.
Topographically, it strongly evokes
A gnarled chunk of old-growth, harshly sheared.


After I’ve finished one of these sessions,
And I’m lumbering about with a sore back
I am often taken aback
By my reflection in the window.

I see an odd, effeminate young man,
Replete with loose cheeks, neotonous
Absence of cheekbone definition,
And a narrow, slightly recessed chin.

Was this the Nordic powerhouse of ten minutes past?


Sunday 5 June 2016

Extract 9

Prefatory note: This is old. I wrote the bulk of this document on the 19th of December 2013. It has been edited sporadically since then.

Two Regional Spelling Bees; Two Strokes of Misfortune Scuttling Hopes and Belying True Abilities

2005 (age 8):
“Breathe,” said the fat, bald man sitting behind the desk. “Breathe,” he repeated.  
“Ok,” Tom said, standing in front of the microphone. He looked around at the crowd of parents sitting to his left, and briefly met eyes with his mother. He looked at the man again. Breathe. Easy. It’s just the same as breath. B R E A T H, breathe. Level 3 is so easy. I can’t believe people are struggling with this stuff. Actually I guess I am pretty smart. He began to speak: “B, R, E, A, T, H, breathe.” He was confident.
But no – the man was reaching her hand over to press the bell: Ding!
What? I thought breathe was the same as breath. Maybe he misheard. Maybe I need to correct him because he didn’t hear what I said… Or maybe I am wrong. I must be wrong.
“The correct answer is B, R, E, A, T, H, E. You’ll have to sit down now.”
That sounds so weird. An e on the end? Really? Dammit. Why did I have to get that word? Everyone else got such basic ones. Dammit. I’m better than at least ten other people still in. Dammit. I could’ve won.
He sidled slowly, head bowed, through the aisle of parents seated on plastic blue chairs. At last he reached the seat next to his mum.
“Argh,” he said as he sat down next to her. As soon as he had got comfortable, he began whispering: “I was sure breathe was the same as breath. I was sure I was right. And I’m so unlucky too coz all the other ones were so easy. I’m so annoyed.” His mum stared back, a sympathetic smile on her face. “I feel like I should still be there… Argh.”
“I thought breathe was the same as breath too. Great minds think alike,” his mum whispered, still smiling.   
“Hmm,” he replied.


2008 (age 11):
He still remembered that terrible day in year 3, when he stood up to spell the word “Breathe”. What an absurd word to get out on. It wasn’t deserved at all. There were so many more long, complex words that could have been his downfall but it had to be breathe. He hadn’t even seen that word written down before that Spelling Bee, that was the problem. At least he’d learnt from his mistake though. You do learn from those mistakes.
He had reached Level 7 this time, a pretty good achievement already – especially for someone who’d made no effort whatsoever to study the official list. But he knew he could get further – a lot further. He had examined and analysed the rest of the field and deduced that he was definitely one of the best spellers there. Some of them were hesitant on words he found easy. Of course some of them weren’t, but still. He’d have to wait and see, when the really big words came up, but at the moment it seemed as if he was right up there – right near the top of the participants.
That said, one of the tough ones, a girl with quite a big nose and long black hair, was standing up now.  
“Clarify,” said the officious lady behind the desk. “Cla-ri-fy.”
“C L A R I F Y, Clarify.”
“Correct. Well done.”
He knew her name: Samantha Lucas. She was that girl he recognised, who he’d met eyes with briefly. She already had developing breasts, which bulged through her tight woollen turtle-neck jumper. Not that he was really aroused by breasts, that would come later he supposed, but anyway she thought he might like him because she was taught piano by his saxophone teacher Alison Clarke and she also had a brother who was a really really amazing saxophone brother.
She’s quite a good piano player. I mean she doesn’t seem that impressive really, but it’s really hard to play the piano so maybe she is about the equivalent level of me in saxophone. Though I’m probably better because people always rave me and how impressive it is to hear me play. Anyway we have a lot in common coz we’re both doing the spelling bee and so she’s probably wondering about how smart and multi-talented I am. And being in Level 7 now I’ve proved myself at least a bit.  
Ding! A slow, tall, big boy got out. He’d been really lucky all the way through with easy words but now this one “Eliminate” had got him out. He’d spelt it with “ait” at the end. Tom couldn’t believe these people were the best spellers in the school. Other people were so stupid.  
Suddenly his stomach twisted; it was his turn. He stood up and sauntered to the microphone.
The officious lady spoke: “Hallucinate.”
“Ok.” He inhaled. He looked around briefly. Ok, simple word, H,A,doubleL,U,C,I,N,A,T,E. I’m ready. “H A double L.” I have to make sure this is right. Ok. “U, N, I, C, A, T, E. Hallucinate.”
Confident he maintained an impassive expression. But no – the lady was reaching her hand over to press the bell: Ding!
What? He was bemused. He contorted his face into a bewildered expression. He looked around him and behind him, the words written on his face, ‘I’m right, I know this word. What’s going on?’ Everyone was silent.
 “The correct answer is H, A, L, L, U, C, I, N, A, T, E.”
He was utterly bewildered. That’s how he spelt it. He searched in the crowd for his mother and Ronnelle, Kimbrian’s mum. He looked at his mum, quizzically. She looked at him sympathetically. He looked round at the other contestants. He was pissed off.
Not again. I’ve gone out in a stupid way again. Goddammit, I hate spelling bees. I always thought I’d make up for year 3 and now… Shit. It’s made me swear in my head.
He sidled slowly, head bowed, through the aisle of parents seated on plastic blue chairs. At last he reached the seat next to his mum.
“Argh” he said as he sat down. “But I was right, I thought I spelt it right,” he whispered.
“I thought you did too.”
Ronnelle leaned over now. “No” she said in her croaky whisper. “I think you spelt it Hallunicate.”
“Ohh,” I whispered. But no I didn’t. No. But maybe I did. I mean, if she noticed a mistake and I’m – dammit, that must have been it. I spelt it dyslexically. I’ve never done that before. Dammit.
Kimbrian, his fellow school representative, was standing up now. Secretly Tom wanted him to fail. Yes that was mean but he didn’t want Kimbrian to beat him, that wouldn’t be right. Especially because Tom was the better speller anyway. Kimbrian was better than him at other stuff, Maths maybe (although Tom had done better in the Maths Olympiad), but he was definitely the better speller.
“Anchor,” said the woman. His word was anchor. That wasn’t so easy, that word. That was probably harder than some. Because there’s that butter brand spelt Anqor and then there’s that place Angkor, but the real spelling’s “anchor” I think, yes “anchor”.
Kimbrian began to speak: “A N.” He paused, a pensive expression on his face. “Q O R.”
Ding! He was gone. He’d fallen. Tom was relieved. It was bad but he was happy that Kimbrian got out on the same round as him. And he could’ve fallen for that word too; Kimbrian didn’t get an easy one. He confused it with the butter though. Tom would have to tell him that.



Lists (sporadically updated)

A Series of Narcissistic, Exhibitionistic Lists (satisfying my tendencies for anal retention) 

Caveat to this series of lists: I have not demarcated genres within my lists of films, books and television shows. This has both pros and cons, as many things do! Simple, three-tier format reflects personal aesthetic preference as follows: whilst comparison is something that everyone engages in, and is an inherent part of aesthetic discourse, I dislike fine-grained comparison (I prefer, for example, Ebert's four-star movie-ranking scheme to the conventional five-star scheme). Whilst this post is indeed periodically, or should I say non-periodically, updated (in fact, the caveat in which this sentence sits used to consist entirely in its first sentence until I added the other sentences this evening, 19/03/2019), I think that some films, and possibly some books, would shift around in my judgment on current re- viewing/reading.

Films I like:
Rank 1:
1917 (2019) (dir. Sam Mendes) (pretty damn good)

As It Is In Heaven (2004) (dir. Kay Pollack) (at the age of 9 (or so), I found this profoundly, profoundly moving)
Apollo 13 (1995) dir. Ron Howard
A Serious Man (2009) (dir. Joel and Ethan Coen)
Audition (1999) (dir. Takashi Miike) (this is quite simply a masterpiece. A movie with multiple interpretations, blending dream, reality, fantasy in a way I have not encountered before or since (similar to Mulholland Drive, but with a greater interpretational ambiguity/complexity)
Badlands (1973) (dir. Terrence Malick)
Barton Fink (1991) (dir. Joel and Ethan Coen) (my favourite film, I think)
The Big Lebowski (1998) (dir. Joel and Ethan Coen) (best dialogue of any film I have ever seen)
Blade Runner 2049 (2016) (dir. Dennis Villeneuve) ([update in 2019: can't think why I put this is rank 1, because I don't remember much liking it... ])
Captain Fantastic (2016) (dir. Matt Ross) (really enjoyed this movie but somewhat ambivalent about its position here in rank 1. Mortensen's acting is superb. I think that being a hippie like Mortensen's character and living in the Tasmanian wilderness or something with a highly intelligent hippie woman with whom I am in love represents a kind of life I would like to have)
Charlie’s Country (2014) (dir. Rolf de Heer) (extremely powerful work)
Dr Strangelove (1964) (dir. Stanley Kubrick)
Full Metal Jacket (1987) (dir. Stanley Kubrick) (cleverest and best anti-war film I have seen)
The Hunter (2011) (dir. Daniel Nettheim)
The Imitation Game (2014) (dir. Morten Tyldum) (apparently this was completely historically inaccurate but, not knowing this, I really enjoyed it at the time)
Kind Hearts and Coronets (1949) (dir. Robert Hamer) (very funny movie)
The Lighthouse (2020) (dir. Robert Eggers) (just brilliant)
Lincoln (2012) (dir. Steven Spielberg)
Lion (2017) (dir. Garth Davis) (cried almost unceasingly throughout)
Little Miss Sunshine (2006) (dir. Jonathan Dayton and Valerie Farys) (the second time I saw this, several years after the first time I saw it, I had tears of cathartic joy streaming down my face at the end (the soundtrack, which I own, is superb also))
The Meaning Of Life (1983) (Monty Python) (by far the best Monty Python film)
The Name of the Rose (1986) (dir. Jean-Jacques Annaud)
Requiem for the American Dream (2015) (dir. Kelly Nyks, Peter Hutchison, Jared Scott)(best Chomsky documentary)
Rise of Skywalker (2019) (dir. J.J. Abrams) (this may be my most controversial opinion yet... no sophisticated reasons for my love of this movie; I just found it really fun and really moving alternately. Really, really enjoyed it. Don't care about changes to Star Wars universe rules and didn't let contrived plot bother me.)

Snowden (2016) (dir. Oliver Stone)
Sweet Country (2018) (dir. Warwick Thompson) (not sure about rank 1)
Tampopo (1985) (dir. Juzo Itami)
Taxi Driver (1974) (dir. Martin Scorsese)
Touching The Void (2003) (dir. Kevin McDonald)
Twin Peaks: Fire Walk with Me (1992) (dir. David Lynch) (I know the critics hated this at the time, but I found it incredibly enthralling (because of the total, dadaist bizarreness (the inclusion of cutting-room-floor stuff, the moments of total incoherence, the occasionally nonsensical dialogue) and really powerful, a much better experience than Blue Velvet (the only other Lych film I've seen, which I wasn't moved by at all and didn't like))
Wall-E (2008) (dir. Andrew Stanton)
12 Years A Slave (2014) (dir. Steve McQueen)(I found this profoundly moving)
Zazie dans le metro (1960) (dir. Louis Malle)
Rank 2:
Amelie (2001) (dir. Jean-Pierre Jeunet)
Annie Hall (1977) (dir. Woody Allen)
Apocalypse Now (1979) (dir. Francis Ford Coppola)
The Austin Powers movies
The Ballad of Buster Scruggs (2018) (dir. Coen brothers) (great until last chapter, which was confusing and anti-climactic)
The Big Short (2015) (dir. Adam McKay)
Bananas (1971) (dir. Woody Allen) (this was literally the first Woody Allen film I have ever seen, and I only saw it a couple of weeks ago, courtesy of a resident of Charles St Forest Lodge (a flat opposite my new lodgings as a post-nest organism))
Being John Malkovich (1999) (dir. Spike Jonze) (also saw this courtesy of above's movie trove (a merely 'virtual' collection acquired disreputably, unfortunately))
Black Swan (2011) (dir. Darren Aronofsky) (I remember liking this just for the nice symbolism)
Blood Diamond (2006) (dir. Edward Zwick)
Born On The Fourth Of July (1989) (dir. Oliver Stone) (probably would like this less now)
Bowling for Columbine (2002) (dir. Michael Moore)
Burn After Reading (2008) (dir. Joel and Ethan Coen)
The Castle (1997) (dir. Rob Sitch)
Children of Men (2006) (dir. Alfonso Cuaron)
Contagion (2011) (dir. Steven Soderbergh)
Deliverance (1972) (dir. John Boorman)
Donnie Darko (2001) (dir. Richard Kelly)
Et Maintenant, On Va Où? (2011) (dir. Nadine Labaki)
Fargo (1996) (dir. Joel and Ethan Coen)
Finding Nemo (2003) (dir. Andrew Stanton and Lee Unkrich)
The Florida Project (2017) (dir. Sean Baker) (very good movie except I had an issue with the ending)
The Force Awakens (2015) (dir. J.J. Abrams)
Get Out (2017) (dir. Jordan Peele) (pretty funny)
Good Boys (2019) (dir. Gene Stupnitsky) (borderline Rank 3, but pretty damn convincing and relatable portrait of the sadness of leaving childhood, and childhood attachments, behind)
Gravity (2013) (dir. Alfonso Cuaron)
Green Book (2018) (dir. Peter Farrelly)
Grizzly Man (2005) (dir. Werner Herzog)
Hidden Figures (2016) (dir. Theodore Melfi)
Hot Fuzz (2007) (dir. Edgar Wright)
Interstellar (2014) (dir. Christopher Nolan)
Jaws (1975) (dir. Steven Spielberg)
Lock, Stock and Two Smoking Barrels (1998) (dir. Guy Ritchie)
Lost Highway (1997) (dir. David Lynch) (a complex movie with an extraordinarily confusing final act... brilliant visuals and music)
Mad Max (1979) (dir. George Miller)
Mad Max: Fury Road (2015) (dir. George Miller)
The Man Who Knew Infinity (2016) (dir. Matthew Brown)
The Martian (2015) (dir. Ridley Scott)
Monsters Inc (2001) (dir. Pete Docter)
Monty Python And The Holy Grail (1975) (dir. Terry Jones and Terry Gilliam)
No Country For Old Men (2007) (dir. Joel and Ethan Coen)
Normandie Nue (2018) (dir. Philippe le Guay)
One Flew Over The Cuckoo’s Nest (1975) (dir. Milos Forman)
The Pianist (2002) (dir. Roman Polanski)
Platoon (1986) (dir. Oliver Stone)
Pride (2014) (dir. Matthew Warchus)
Rogue One (2016) (dir. Gareth Edwards)
Saving Private Ryan (because beach scene) (1998) (dir. Stephen Spielberg)
Shaun Of The Dead (2004) (dir. Edgar Wright)
Shrek (2001) (dir. Andrew Adamson and Vicky Jenson)
The Last Emperor of China (1987) (dir. Bernardo Bertolucci)
The Last Jedi (2017) (dir. Rian Johnson)
The Silence Of The Lambs (1991) (dir. Jonathan Demme)
Team America: World Police (don’t agree with Gary Johnson’s speech at the end: pro-aggression, pro-Imperialist propaganda, and totally false (Matt Parker and Trey Stone are stupid, unreflective “Libertarians”)) (2004) (dir. Trey Parker and Matt Stone)
Ten Canoes (2006) (dir. Rolf de Heer)
Up (2009) (dir. Pete Docter and Bob Peterson)
Velvet Buzzsaw (2019) (dir. Dan Gilroy)
Les Visiteurs (1993) (dir. Jean-Marie Poire)
Rank 3:
The Adventures of Barry McKenzie (1972) (dir. Bruce Beresford) 
Apocalypto (2006) (dir. Mel Gibson) (liked this despite its complete ahistoricality and its elements of crudeness)
Arrival (2016) (dir. Dennis Villeneuve)
The Black Balloon (2008) (dir. Elissa Down)
The Departed (2006) (dir. Martin Scorsese)
Despicable Me (2010) (dir. Pierre Coffin and Chris Renaud)
The Elephant Man (1980) (dir. David Lynch) (not easy to watch, and not exactly glad I watched it, but a good movie)
Ghost in the Shell (2017) (dir. Rupert Sanders)
Hail Caesar (2016) (dir. Coen brothers)
Her (2015) by Spike Jonze
Invictus (2009) (dir. Clint Eastwood)
Knives Out (2019) (dir. Rian Johnson) (solid entertainment)
Sorry to Bother You (2018) (dir. Boots Riley)
Sorry We Missed You (2019) (dir. Ken Loach) (better, though very different from, the film directly above it on this list, and possibly deserving Rank 2, but it is somewhat witty to place them adjacently)
Step Brothers (2008) (dir. Adam McKay) (in my opinion, this is the best Ferrell movie... I think the reason is that his improv style is very stupid and unsophisticated -- works perfectly for this movie)
This Is England  (2006) (dir. Shane Meadows)
Train to Busan (2016) (dir. Yeon Sang-ho) (a visually stunning and exciting zombie horror movie; predictable in some ways but still a good ride)
The Twelve Monkeys (1995) (dir. Terry Gilliam) (Gilliam plays with our sense of reality in a ham-fisted way (the most plausible interpretation given the clues presented and knowledge of everyday reality eventually becomes, unambiguously and decisively, the wrong interpretation, even though this leaves many things seeming profoundly odd/unexplained), but the plot is overall very enjoyable and the representation of time-travel is logical, in contrast to, say, Looper)
Vivarium (2019) (dir. Lorcan Finnegan) (extremely hard to watch -- too brutal -- but definitely a 'good movie' in its execution of this brutality)

Books I like:
Rank 1: 
Ages of Discord (2016) by Peter Turchin (wonderful!)
The Better Angels of our Nature (2011) by Steven Pinker (certainly don’t agree with everything in this book, however)
Buzz: The Nature and Necessity of Bees (2018) by Thor Hanson (top read on bees... who knew that flowers as we know them co-evolved with bees, and bees only originated in the late Cretaceous (that is to say, dinosaurs didn't exist around flowers as we know them)?)
Catch 22 (1961) by Joseph Heller (really liked this when I was 14)
Collapse (2005) by Jared Diamond (an absurdly wonderful book)
Dancing with Strangers (2003) by Inga Clendinnen (Clendinnen's imaginative empathy is a wonder to behold, in this highly engaging short work)
Debt: The First 5000 Years by David Graeber (since I found out that it has lots of shitty scholarship, it no longer has Rank 1 in my mind, but I'm keeping it here for posterity or some shit)
Debunking Economics (Second Edition, 2011) by Steve Keen
Dubliners (1914) by James Joyce (didn't love every story, but some I loved)
Every Thing Must Go (2006) by James Ladyman and Don Ross (used to be in Rank 2 but I read it for a second time after doing philosophy of biology and now I'm much more of a true believer)
Extreme Money: Masters of the Universe and the Cult of Risk (2011) by Satyajit Das (never quite finished - but is a really superb book, dense with information and vibrant storytelling, and scintillatingly written)
A Farwell to Ice: A Report from the Arctic (2017) by Peter Wadhams (gonna post extracts from this soon)
Foundations of Language: Brain, Meaning, Grammar, Evolution (2001) by Ray Jackendoff (what a book! Amazing)
The Future Eaters (1994) by Tim Flannery
The General Theory of Employment, Interest and Money (1936) by John Maynard Keynes
Globalisation and its Discontents (2001) by Joseph Stiglitz
The Greens (1996) by Bob Brown and Peter Singer
Gulliver's Travels (1726) by Jonathan Swift (read about half of this when I was 13; slowly finishing as of 6/02/17 (British/Australia date representation) (though gets very boring after Liliput and Brobdingnag))
Guns, Germs and Steel (1997) by Jared Diamond
Heart of Darkness (1899) by Joseph Conrad
Hiroshima (1946) by John Hersey
In Gods We Trust: the Evolutionary Basis of Religion (2001) by Scott Atran
Kill All Normies (2017) by Angela Nagle (worth reading! ... although her Baffler article, "The New Man of 4 Chan" had most of these ideas already)
Killing the Host: How Debt and Financial Parasites Destroy the Global Economy (2015) by Michael Hudson
The Lady with Lapdog and Other Stories (1964) by Anton Chekhov
The Language Instinct (1994) by Steven Pinker
Limits to Growth: The 30-Year Update (2001) by various authors
The Lizard Eaters (1964) by Douglas Lockwood (enjoyed a huge amount in - was it 2009? - when I picked it up at some touristy bookstore near Uluru)
Mathematics, Science and Epistemology: Philosophical Papers Volume 2 (1978) by Imre Lakatos, ed. John Worrall and Gregory Currie
Moby Dick (1851) by Herman Melville (I finished this and really loved it. Very clever and deep book.)
Oblivion (2004) by David Foster Wallace
Other Minds (2017) by Peter Godfrey-Smith (who is a very good philosopher and a very lucid writer!)
The Price of Inequality (2011) by Joseph Stiglitz
A Portrait of the Artist as a Young Man (1916) by James Joyce
The Road (2006) by Cormac McCarthy
Scale: The Universal Laws of Life and Death in Organisms, Cities and Companies (2017) by Geoffrey West (I enjoyed this book a lot overall. Demonstrates the power of the a priori and importance of developing abstract theory in all disciplines of human scholarship, although of course I think plenty of stuff in the book, particularly the later parts, is on pretty shaky ground.)
The Science of Language (2012) (Dialogues between James McGilvray and Noam Chomsky on linguistics, philosophy, philosophy of science, philosophy of cognitive science, evolutionary psychology, politics, philosophy of rhetoric, irrationality)
The Singular Universe and the Reality of Time (2014) by Lee Smolin and Roberto Mangabeira Unger (Smolin's third of this epic is far more concise, far less repetitive and far more incisive)
A Short History of Nearly Everything (2003) by Bill Bryson (first read in year 7)
Thinking, Fast and Slow (2011) by Daniel Kahneman
Throwin Way Leg (1999) by Tim Flannery
The Turning (2005) by Tim Winton
Van Diemen's Land (2009) by James Boyce (really excellent history book; well-researched, entertaining, sharp arguments)
War and Peace and War (2005) by Peter Turchin
What is this thing called science? (1978/1999) by A.F. Chalmers
Where Song Began (2014) by Tim Low (hugely interesting and excellent, learnt a lot)
White Noise (1985) by Don DeLillo
The Wizard and the Prophet (2018) by Charles Mann (a really brilliant book which has had a big impact on my thinking (roused me from a dogmatic pessimistic slumber), even if it suffers from a kind of simplistic overapplication of the titular dichotomy in the middle chapters (the categorisation works best, imho, as a Platonic thing, i.e. not everyone has to fall into one group or the other (Mann himself, e.g., is presumably neither Wizard nor Prophet), but it sometimes seems like Mann slides away from this))
Who Rules the World? (2016) by Noam Chomsky
Who We Are and How We Got Here (2018) by David Reich (an information-packed book which taught me a vast amount)
Rank 2:
A Banquet of Consequences (2015) by Satyajit Das
The Blank Slate (2002) by Steven Pinker
Blood Meridian (1985) by Cormac McCarthy
The Captain Underpants series (my childhood self would have ticked this one)
Can we avoid another financial crisis? (2017) by Steve Keen (very short - shorter than two, maybe three of the essays I have posted on this blog. Still worth buying)
Catcher in the Rye (1951) by J.D. Salinger
Chomsky and his Critics (2003) ed. Louise M. Anthony and Norbert Hornstein
Cooper’s Creek (1963) by Alan Moorehead
Crime and Punishment (1866) by Fyodor Dostoevsky (never finished, much as I never finished Oliver Twist or Great Expectations)
The Diary of a Wimpy Kid series (my 13-year-old self would have ticked this one)
The Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire (1776) by Edward Gibbon (never finished the condensed one-volume edition I was reading)
Down Under (2001) by Bill Bryson
The Essential Chomsky (1999) 
Farenheit 451 (1953) by Ray Bradbury
The Hidden Life of Trees (2016) by Peter Wohlleben
A History of Western Philosophy (1945) by Bertrand Russell (haven’t quite finished)
How the Mind Works (1997) by Steven Pinker
The Horrible Histories series (my childhood self would have ticked this one)
If This is a Man (1947) by Primo Levi
Infinite Jest (1996) by David Foster Wallace (would probably like this less now; at time, loved bits, found other parts really tedious (e.g. everything involving Marathe and, in fact, everything involving the Quebecois terrorists generally))
Innate (2018) by Kevin Mitchell (generally very important and sound systems dynamics perspective on the developmental process, interesting thoughts about noise and good argument that heaps of shit is innate without being genetic. Rest of book sorta generic psych stuff that's a bit more dodgy and got a little tedious)
Keynes: The Return of the Master (2009) by Robert Skidelsky
Keynes Hayek: The Clash that Defined Modern Economics by Nicholas Wapshott (the first book I ever read on economics)
The Kraken Wakes (1953) by John Wyndham (read because of my friend S.M., to whom I am immensely grateful (for this recommendation and loan, and other things))
Manufacturing Consent (1988) by Noam Chomsky and Edward Herman (only read pdf online, and only perfunctorily)
Mr Stuart's Track (2006) by John Bailey
My Country: Stories, Essays and Speeches (2019) by David Marr (an essay collection covering more than four decades of writing by one of my favourite journalists. It's long but, honestly, could be a lot longer. For me, I actually enjoyed the personal, biographical essays/excerpts (mostly residing at the front of the book) more than anything else, although it's also very much worth re-reading his writing on Howard. Reason not top rank is that some of the pieces included are kind of boring and feel irrelevant -- it's not wall-to-wall gold.)
Europe: A Natural History (2018) by Tim Flannery (another excellent Flannery book (but not a Flannery classic, I feel) packed full of information covering a very wide range of scientific fields, tracing the ecological history of Europe from the late Cretaceous to the present along with amusing tales about the scientists who uncovered the major insights)
On the Plurality of Worlds (1989) by David Kellogg Lewis
On What Matters vols 1 and 2 (2011) by Derek Parfit (don’t think this book is entirely wrong either, unlike most philosophers)
The Open Society and its Enemies (1945) by Karl Popper (only skimread this book (using an online pdf) and used CTRL-f a lot, but what I found was great)
The Pale King (2011) by David Foster Wallace
Reasons and Persons (1984) by Derek Parfit
The Stuff of Thought: Language as a Window into the Human Mind (2007) by Steven Pinker
Super-Imperialism: The Origin and Fundamentals of US World Dominance (2003, second edition; first edition, 1975) by Michael Hudson
Talking to the Enemy (2011) by Scott Atran
Ultrasociety: How 10000 Years of War made Humans the Greatest Cooperators (2015) by Peter Turchin
Who Stole Feminism? (1994) by Christina Hoff Sommers (though I don't approve of anything she has done since)
Why only us? (2015) by Robert Berwick and Noam Chomsky
Rank 3:
Cloudstreet (1991) by Tim Winton
Falter (2019) by Bill McKibben (sort of lacks rigour; a lot of pretty rank speculation... I hadn't read a McKibben book before this -- from what I had read of his previously, I thought it would be better than this... not to say it's bad)
Galileo's Middle Finger (2016) by Alice Dreger
Naturalism Without Mirrors (2011) by Huw Price (too vague far too often)
The Sceptical Feminist (1980) by Janet Radcliffe Richards
Superintelligence: Paths, Dangers, Strategies (2014) by Nick Bostrom
Truth (2005) by Simon Blackburn (not useful to me in the least)
The Utopia of Rules: On Technology, Stupidity and the Secret Joys of Bureaucracy (2015) by David Graeber (some lapidary stuff plus plenty of fanaticism and shitty arguments)

TV Shows I like:
Rank 1:
Black Mirror (2011, 2013, 2016)
Blue Planet II  (2017) (just fucking superlative!)
Breaking Bad (2008-2013) (as of March 16 2018, just started watching this last week (maybe the end of the week before) via US Netflix via NordVPN. More than half-way through the second season now. The first season was perhaps the best TV I have ever seen. I agree with H.'s assessment of the show that I remember from 5 years ago, when he was watching it: "Impeccable".)
The Flight of the Conchords  (2007, 2009) ((have watched both seasons from start to finish probably seven times or more)
Friday Night Dinner (2011, 2012, 2014, 2016) (“Martin” is incredibly similar to my own dad, and “Jim” is such a brilliant character)
The Gogs (1994)
Into the Universe with Stephen Hawking (2010)
Jeeves and Wooster (1990-93)
Review with Myles Barlow (2008, 2010)
Shaun Micallef’s Mad as Hell (2012-)
Tim and Eric Awesome Show Great Job! (2007-10) (season 1 is the worst season (but still has some superb episodes), 4 is particularly brilliant)
Tim and Eric Nite Live (2007-08) (some really stellar episodes, eg election special and Valentine’s special)
Walking with Beasts (2001) (watched this about a million times when I was a kid)
Walking with Dinosaurs (1999) (watched this about a million times when I was a kid)
Wonders of the Universe (2011) (Brian Cox)
Wonders of Life (2013) (Brian Cox)
The Young Ones (1982-84)
Rank 2:
Blackadder (1983, 1986, 1987, 1989)
Black Books (2000-04)
The Chaser’s War on Everything (2006-09)
Downton Abbey (2010-15)
The Fast Show (1994-97)
Hard Quiz (2016)
Little Britain (2003-06)
(First 11 seasons of) South Park (1997-2007)
The Thick of It (2005, 2007, 2009, 2012)
Rank 3:
Adventure Time (2010-) (had this recommended to me as a 16 year old. Never watched a single episode until a few days ago (March 2019). Enjoyed the first few episodes of the first season.)
The IT Crowd (2006, 2007, 2008, 2010)
Newstopia (2007-08)
Talkin' 'Bout Your Generation (2009-12)

Musicians, Composers and bands I like:
Rank 1:
Anton Bruckner
Antonin Dvorak
Arvo Part
Augie March (Strange Bird is their best album by a significant margin)
Beirut
Dimitri Shostakovich
Fela Kuti
Gustav Holst
Porcupine Tree (a really wonderful prog band (though I almost exclusively listen to just three of the albums in their extensive discography, In Absentia, Deadwing and Fear of a Blank Planet (these albums all have Gavin Harrison as drummer (an out-of-this-world musician), and showcase Steven Wilson's electric guitar range and atmospheric composition at its finest (unfortunately, Wilson’s lyrics are uniformly terrible))))
Pyotr Illyich Tchaikovsky
Radiohead (obviously)
Sergei Rachmaninoff (my favourite composer (sends me into convulsions) (as you can see, I really like the Russian Romantics))
The Shins (best indie-rock band (Chutes Too Narrow is a masterpiece of the genre))
Sufjan Stevens (I adore The Age of Adz, Illinois and Michigan, and I think Carrie and Lowell is a terrific album also)
Yann Tiersen
XTC (first got into XTC when I was 5, through my dad)
Rank 2:
Alexander Borodin
Andrew Bird
Aphex Twin
Arcade Fire (Funeral is the best album by a significant margin)
The Beach Boys (/Brian Wilson (Smile is a brilliant album))
The Beatles
Bjork
Brian Eno (I like Another Green World best – not that interested in the ambient stuff for which he is most famous)
Camille Saint-Saens
The Cat Empire
Cesaria Evora
The Clash
Crowded House
Dan Kelly
David Bowie (70s stuff and Blackstar)
Devotchka (only Little Miss Sunshine soundtrack)
Elvis Costello
Felix Mendelssohn
Frank Ticheli
Gustav Mahler
Hector Berlioz
Igor Stravinsky
James Carter (amazingly expressive and cool jazz found here: https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=q_d0I97ZNl0&t=2s)
Jimi Hendrix
Jean Sibelius
Johannes Brahms
Johann Sebastian Bach
Josh Pyke
King Crimson
Kraftwerk
Led Zeppelin
Ludwig van Beethoven
Maurice Ravel
Max Richter
Mighty Sparrow
Miles Davis
Nick Cave and the Bad Seeds
Nikolai Rimsky-Korsakov
Paul Kelly
Percy Grainger (for Horkstow Grange)
Pink Floyd
Richard Strauss
Sergei Prokofiev
Steven Wilson
The Smiths
Tame Impala 
Tom Waits
Wilco
Yello
Rank 3:
Blur
Boy and Bear                                                      
Broken Bells
Cloud Control
Doves
Fleet Foxes
Goldfrapp
Gotye (favourite song is "State of the Art")
Kate Bush
Madness
Mental as Anything
Modest Mouse
Modest Mussorgsky
Of Montreal
Pixies
R.E.M
Sigur Ros
Something for Kate
*Speaking in early 2018, I've become super into watching Jazz concerts on Youtube since a few months ago, but it's a bit odd adding people like James Morrison, Dave Brubeck, Bobby Militello, Troy Roberts, Wynton Marsalis, Olivier Franc, Chris Potter or whoever else to this list.. Too many performers

Activities I like:
Being in a sublime environment, eg in one of Australia’s hundreds of excellent National Parks (higher pleasure)
Having an intimate conversation with someone (mostly higher pleasure)
Listening to really good music (extremely rich version of base pleasure, especially if it’s Rachmaninoff)
Writing something that I believe to be of value (higher pleasure)
Engaging in good banter with others (base pleasure)
Watching a good film (usually a mixture of higher and base pleasures)
Reading a good book (sometimes only a higher pleasure, sometimes both)

*Special Bonus List*
Unpopular opinions of mine:
I don’t like the films of Quentin Tarantino (vulgar, garish, corrosive to the soul and intellect)
I don’t like Seinfeld (seems little better than other American sitcoms which I also don’t like (singled it out because it’s so often singled out for praise by slightly intellectual or indie types))
I have listened to a fair amount of rap and not appreciated or enjoyed any of it (one reason is that I have a very low threshold for misogyny)
I have a Theological revulsion to porn (cross through sentence on 19/03/2019, at age of 22 and 1 month. Because.... just because)
**Speaking as 20/almost 21 -year-old, I somewhat cringe to read the following** I have very little interest in travel (I can find beauty anywhere, eg my backyard). I also hate Paris. **I still practise Stoic reasoning about happiness and I still try to 'see beauty everywhere' (I mean, the family-home backyard is actually really beautiful, 'objectively'), but I think the sentiment expressed here is extreme (and I was being edgy about Paris because I had a deeply miserable time there on French exchange). Not that long ago, I told this girl who I was interested in that I "used to have the really edgy view" that travel was pointless, and she didn't understand that I had changed my mind, which frustrated me, because it made me seem weird (weird in the way nobody wants to be weird) and very different from her, someone who had travelled a lot. I actually am extremely keen to visit more places around the world, as most people are!**
While I am (evidently) an avid listener of classical music, I find Mozart staid and boring (I generally prefer Romantic shit in any case (even Beethoven, who bridges the gap between Classical and Romantic, is too unadventurous for me)).
**Speaking as 20/almost 21 -year-old, I somewhat cringe to read the following** I don’t like looking at paintings or sculptures, and have never enjoyed a single art gallery experience in my life (contemporary art is, of course, particularly bad; I absolutely loathed MONA in Hobart (I see beauty in the everyday world (including urban landscapes), and in National Parks, and I therefore don’t really see the point of art galleries (and I happily concede that I sound like a philistine, but I simply don’t know how to ‘appreciate’ visual art without spiralling into highly self-conscious recursive thought vortexes about the fact that I am in a highly contrived situation trying to make myself appreciate a bit of canvas on a white wall surrounded by other people looking serious and thoughtful, and that’s inherently ridiculous etc)).  **I can, I think, avoid descending into those silly "thought vortexes" now...I try at least. Certainly, though, I would still much prefer to spend money on a camping trip than art gallery tickets.**
**Speaking as 20/almost 21 -year-old, I somewhat cringe to read the following** I think expensive restaurants are pretentious shams and I believe that, if you have a clear-eyed maximally unpretentious attitude, you can recognise that hearty, home-cooked meals are actually better (intrinsically more satisfying) than the deconstructed, ‘subtle’, ‘complex’ fare you get at $200-a-head venues. **I was never that confident about this even when I wrote it; I have had both good and bad experiences at real fancy places.**
I’m not a cognitivist or non-cognitivist about ethics (my position is unnameable). **Silly parenthetical comment, but first part is true. I think ethical judgments within the context of formal moral reasoning in philosophy definitely are truth-apt (if they are treated as truth-apt and we have some kind of framework of evaluation, clearly they are!), but I think perhaps that an expressivist or Speech Act analysis may make more sense for everyday discourse**
I’m a scientific naturalist who dislikes scientism (mainly scientistic attitudes towards philosophy).
My politics are very unusual. Roughly characterisable as ‘far left’ (I hate all politicians and I hate the economic establishment and all major economic bodies, I distrust all ‘concentrations of power’, and I believe the world is radically unjust), however I do also have a somewhat tragic view of human nature (more Hobbesian than Rousseauian), don’t like Identity Politics, don’t like Postmodernism, don’t like most far leftists, don’t think we could do without a police force, support nuclear **much more ambivalent now, with increased understanding of difficulty of safe waste disposal**, recognise the powerful dynamism of capitalism, think the idea of a proletarian revolution is totally harebrained etc. For a few months now, I have called myself a Post-Keynesian Moral Anarchist, which is a completely novel term with an intricate meaning that no-one on earth understands but me. **The most significant development in my politics after the time at which this was last updated is that I have decided that my major political preoccupation is ecology and the environment. I am desperately concerned with declining arable land and water shortages (as the population grows on a planet saturated with pesticides and other pollutants, with fertile areas plagued by problems such as salinisation, erosion, overgrazing and insect decline, and more extreme weather due to climate change potentially leading to major crop loss and general upheaval), I am deeply concerned with other effects of pollution on human and animal health, and I am strongly committed to protecting areas of awesome natural beauty, and precious ecosystems, across the world. To me, protecting the environment subsumes all other political concerns - and I see this almost as a rational requirement for a consequentialist in the midst of climate breakdown. The shit is beginning to hit the fan.**