Search This Blog

Wednesday 28 June 2017

The Problem of Individuals and Species in Biology, and Ontic Structural Realism

To start off this document, here is a very slightly extended version of my uni essay on problem of biological individuality, wherein I rhapsodise over Peter Godfrey-Smith (first ever sub-80 philosophy essay mark but only because I didn't have enough words to actually make my case properly (fucking stupid Neoliberal bureaucratic system where even in a very poorly subscribed unit you have extremely stringent, oppressive word limits)). (Also I think that just adding the sentences I added in this version would have pushed my mark significantly higher (the original was insufficiently explicit about the shortcomings of Clarke's account)).

3.      What is the problem of biological individuality? Compare and contrast two theories of biological individuality, and explain whether they are successful or not.

The “problem of biological individuality” is the problem of how to give a general account of what defines a ‘biological individual’ across all species to which evolutionary theory applies, given the incredible diversity of life. Ellen Clarke [2010] holds that this is a serious issue because of how crucial the notion of an organism is to our understanding of biological evolution, the very concept of “fitness”, and more. In this essay, I will compare Peter Godfrey Smith’s elaborate, continuous account of biological individuality with Ellen Clarke’s own, much simpler functional (and also continuous) account of biological individuality. I will suggest that they are both very impressive taxonomical efforts, but that Godfrey-Smith’s has the greater balance of virtues, on account of (what I believe to be) its greater comprehensiveness and greater potential to defuse controversies.

In her well-cited 2010 paper “The Problem of Biological Individuality”, Ellen Clarke concisely and effectively explains the titular problem, and why one should care. She begins the paper by explicating the centrality of this idea of ‘the organism’ to the biological sciences. This notion of the biological individual is perhaps most important for its starring role in our understanding of evolution: Darwin formulated his theory of evolution in terms of biological individuals, the “received view of biological evolution takes the organism as “the basic unit of selection””, and, as Dawkins admits, even the ‘gene-centrist’ cannot hope to dispense with the biological individual in evolutionary theorising (even in the mathematics) [Dawkins, 1982: 251]. As Clarke puts it: “It is hard to overemphasize the importance of individuals within the Modern Synthesis. They are central to the inner logic of evolution by natural selection, according to which evolution occurs because of the differential survival and reproduction of individuals” [2010: 313]. The organism also plays a massive role, albeit slightly more hidden, in various other sub-fields of the biological sciences “such as medicine, developmental biology, immunology, ecology, and the reductionist sciences such as molecular or cell biology” [313]. Finally, organisms are what population biologists count!
The trouble, of course, is that, despite the immense scientific utility of this concept, philosophers of biology as of 2010 only had a long list of competing criteria for describing biological individuality, all of which individually seem to admit of counterexamples and define strongly “non-overlapping classes” – and this vagueness allows for scientific conflict as well. Clarke discusses, in particular, 13 different candidates for criteria (all biological “properties” in some very wide sense) which could do the work of “differentiating individuals from parts and groups”. [1] Although some are more promising than others, the case studies Clarke introduces demonstrate (I think) that there is not a clear mix-and-match solution.  In her follow-up 2013 paper “The Multiple Realizability of Biological Individuals”, Clarke also shows that the problem has practical import by pointing to some of the scientific controversies that could have been avoided if biologists had agreed on what counts as an individual. The first controversy she cites is the “long-standing debate amongst plant scientists about whether vegetatively produced plants […] ought to add to the parent plant’s fitness or not” [414]. Another, more general one she describes is the long-running controversy in evolutionary theory over ‘levels of selection’: in particular, over propositions like “selection always acts at the level of the individual”. She suggests – rightly, I think – that these debates would dissipate a lot of heat if the interlocutors acceded to a common account of biological individuality (especially to deal with what Godfrey-Smith calls the “problem cases” of collective entities like “ant and bee colonies, and lichens” [Godfrey-Smith, 2012: 3]).
In the same 2013 paper, however, Clarke goes on to propose a solution to her own problem. Her big idea is to ‘compress’ several of the competing properties she highlighted in “The Problem of Biological Individuality” (sex, bottlenecks, germ-soma separation, policing mechanisms, spatial boundaries, and immune response) into a simpler and more economical ‘functional’ definition. The first component of Ellen Clarke’s functional definition is the “policing mechanism”, which she claims is a robust enough functional property to constitute a necessary condition for biological individuality. She defines a policing mechanism as “any mechanism that inhibits the capacity of an object to undergo within-object selection” [2013: 421]. Clarke thinks that as well as helping to end debates over the priority of this or that specific policing mechanism, this kind of functional definition can put us in a better position “to recognize real-life structures that play the desired role” [422]. She justifies this claim by giving a number examples of such real-life structures, including “Resource exchange, synchronized/vertical transmission (especially “co-dispersal”), spatial contiguity or engulfment, the immune system, maternal control of early development, and worker policing” [423].
Of course, whilst having a “policing mechanism” is a necessary condition for something to be a biological individual, Clarke recognises that it is by no means sufficient, on account of its being a “negative” condition: for example, the non-organism that is a human muscle cell “has ample policing mechanisms to cement common purpose amongst its component organelles and genetic material” [423]. The necessary positive mechanism for Clarke then is the “positive capacity to undergo natural selection at its own level” [423]. After relating this suggestion to the biological function of sex, Clarke extends this insight into a second functional criterion for biological individuality: a “demarcation mechanism”, which she defines as “any mechanism that increases or maintains the capacity of an object to undergo between object selection” [424]. Like policing mechanisms, demarcation mechanisms are highly multiply realisable. For example, spatial boundaries and immunity can often play a ‘demarcating’ role. Demarcation, Clarke claims, is also “essential to an evolutionary transition” [426].  As she explains, “Evolutionary transitions in individuality can be viewed as a failure to meet the demarcation challenge on the part of the lower-level individual. Mitochondria, for example, have lost their biological individuality because they became subsumed within eukaryotic cells” [426].
Clarke’s two mechanisms are, she thinks, sufficient criteria for biological individuality. She holds that “Biological individuals are all and only those objects that possess both kinds of individuating mechanism” [427]. This may seem like a very bold claim, but Clarke is anxious to point out is that the very nature of these mechanisms ensures that individuality is a continuous concept. She makes the important observation that “by incrementally increasing an object’s capacity biological individuals for heritable variance in fitness, compared to the capacity of its parts, individuating mechanisms can gradually push the object through an evolutionary transition in individuality” [430]. Indeed, she argues convincingly that it is necessary to recognise this kind of continuity in individuation in order to understand how evolutionary transitions happen at all.
In his 2012 paper “Darwinian Individuals”, Peter Godfrey-Smith outlines a somewhat more complicated account of biological individuality than Clarke’s. Although it has many features in common with Clarke’s, and whilst it’s not clear that the two accounts are in any kind of strong tension, Godfrey-Smith’s separation of two partly-overlapping sub-genres of biological individuals, “Darwinian individuals” and “Organisms”, and his very detailed accounts of each, lead to a scheme which is extremely good at dealing with ‘borderline’ cases, and yet produces much more definite entailments about specific cases than Clarke’s account. Clarke, I think, effectively argues for the value of a ‘functional’ definition of biological individuality, but I will argue that Godfrey-Smith’s work shows that a broadly functionalist approach can be combined with specific biological properties to produce a more complete overall account of biological individuality.
Both Clarke and Godfrey-Smith are chiefly concerned with coming up with an account of biological individuality fully in tune with the usage of “individual” within evolutionary theory. Clarke’s account is peculiarly devoted to what Godfrey-Smith specifically demarcates as the “Darwinian individual”, since her two individuating mechanisms have the ultimate function of enhancing “heritable variation in fitness”. In Godfrey-Smith’s attempt to come up with an account of the Darwinian individual, reproduction is the key factor (whereas for Clarke it goes along for the ride to some extent). Like Clarke, however, Godfrey-Smith is mainly concerned with “collective” individuals in formulating his account. Unlike Clarke, Godfrey-Smith’s account is explicitly continuous: he sees Darwinian individuality in terms of three dimensions, with the most exemplary cases measuring ‘high up’ in all three and non-Darwinian individuals measuring very ‘low down’ in all three. The first dimension or “parameter” is B, which stands for “bottleneck”. By this, Godfrey-Smith means any kind of “narrowing” that “marks the divide between generations […] often to a single cell” (as in humans) [2012: 6]. The second dimension is G, which stands for “germline”. G measures the degree of reproductive specialization within a collective. This property helps usefully distinguish kinds of ‘eusocial’ species. For example, in honey bee colonies “the queen reproduces (along with the male "drones"), and the female workers do not” (high score for G), whereas “In other insects, including other bees, there is no reproductive division of labor” (low score for G) [7]. The third and final, more functional dimension is I, which stands for “integration”. This does the ‘work’ of parts of both of Clarke’s individuating mechanisms, involving a “general division of labor (aside from that in G), the mutual dependence of parts, and the maintenance of a boundary between a collective and what is outside it” [7]. Godfrey-Smith uses this three-dimensional account to come up with an ingenious 1×1×1 cubic visualisation of where various species ‘sit’ in terms of their level of Darwinian individuality. Humans (and other mammals, marsupials, birds, many amphibians and many fish) are prototypical Darwinian individuals, with perfect (1,1,1) scores for each parameter; the Volvox carteri alga also scores highly with 1, 1, 0.5 (B, G, I); clonal colonies like the Aspen ramet scores 0.5, 0.5, 1; sponges score 0, 0, 0.5; and a buffalo herd is not a Darwinian individual at all, since it scores 0, 0, 0.
It seems to me that Godfrey-Smith’s ability to represent his classifications so elegantly represents a distinct advantage of his account over Clarke’s. In this, I fully endorse Daniel Dennett’s praise of the same diagrams in his review of Godfrey-Smiths’s 2009 book Reflections on Darwinian Populations and Natural Selection.
Godfrey-Smith then moves onto his account of ‘organismality’, where an ‘organism’ is understood as something distinct from a Darwinian individual – a concept that Clarke does not have. The way Godfrey-Smith defines an organism is as follows: “Systems comprised of diverse parts which work together to maintain the system's structure, despite turnover of material, by making use of sources of energy and other resources from their environment” [12]. This he calls the traditional, ‘metabolic view of a biological individual. Ultimately, the combination of this continuous organism concept and the Darwinian individual concept allows for Godfrey-Smith to define biological individuality for all of life. Many biological individuals – like humans, or fruit flies – are both Darwinian individuals and organisms. A much smaller number would be classified as relatively prototypical examples of Darwinian individuals but not organisms: “scaffolded reproducers” like viruses, along with chromosomes and genes [16]. Finally, some organisms are not Darwinian individuals. The more significant cases in this category “are certain kinds of symbiotic associations” [16]. Godfrey-Smith cites Dupre and Malley [2009] as showing that “most or all plants and animals live in close associations with symbionts” [16]. One specific example of a very close symbiotic relationship whose significance has only recently been uncovered is that between various tree species and “mycorrhizal fungi” which connect root systems in forests such that trees can ‘communicate’ threats and distribute resources to other trees in stress [Macfarlane, 2016]. (Basically, such tree-fungi fusions seem to fall under the category of organisms that are not Darwinian individuals (the fungi are crucial to the tree's fitness, as in the other example of a symbiont that is an organism but not a Darwinian individual which I'm about to discuss, but the tree and the fungi do not reproduce together, as one, in contrast to the aphid-Buchnera symbiosis.) Godfrey-Smith’s best example of an organism (albeit a non-prototypical organism) that is not a Darwinian individual is the “squid-Vibrio combination”, which has a “horizontally transmitted symbiont” as opposed to the “vertically transmitted symbiont” of the oft-cited aphid-Buchnera symbiosis. Even though the squid has evolved six internal ‘chambers’ designed to take in the bacteria that create a luminescent, moon-light-like patterning on their body and help them avoid avian predation at night, the fact that the squid are not born with these bacteria inside them means the partnership does not count as a Darwinian individual.
I think the big advantage Godfrey-Smith’s complicated account has over Clarke’s much more economical one is that, whereas he can apply his scheme to these exotic cases and produce definite (albeit ‘continuous’) verdicts, such verdicts do not directly fall out of Clarke’s considerably looser scheme (it seems to me that Clarke's account makes it very hard to disentangle the very relevant differences between the type of symbionts I discussed, for example). Clarke, in fact, ends her 2013 paper by insisting on the implausibility of a general system of classification for all of life – and yet it seems to me that that’s effectively what Godfrey-Smith achieves.
Reference List

Clarke, Ellen (2010). “The Problem of Biological Individuality”, Biological Theory, 5 (4): 312-325.
(2013). “The Multiple Realizability of Biological Individuals”, Journal of Philosophy 110 (8): 413-435.

Dawkins, Richard (1982). The Extended Phenotype, Oxford University Press.

Dennett, Daniel (2011). “Homunculi rule: Reflections on Darwinian populations and natural selection by Peter Godfrey Smith”, Biology and Philosophy 26 (4): 475-488.

Godfrey-Smith, Peter (2012). Frédéric Bouchard and Philippe Huneman (eds.) “Darwinian Individuals” in From Groups to Individuals: Perspectives on Biological Associations and Emerging Individuality, MIT Press. Accessed from:
<http://www.petergodfreysmith.com/PGS_Darwinian_Individuals.pdf>

Macfarlane, Robert (2016). “The Secrets of the Wood Wide Web”, The New Yorker, August Issue:
<http://www.newyorker.com/tech/elements/the-secrets-of-the-wood-wide-web>

Uncited:
Wilson, Robert A. and Barker, Matthew, "The Biological Notion of Individual", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2017 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.): <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/biology-individual/>.


Now that you've read that essay, I'm just start talking about how what you just read relates to the very deepest issues in metaphysics. Here goes.

I think that the better-known ‘species’ problem in the philosophy of biology is highly analogous to this problem of ‘biological individuality’, and I think that the metaphysics of Structural Realism helps us to see these similarities more clearly. It is, however, very complicated to show this, so bear with me.
There’s a great Philip Kitcher quote in a 2012 book I haven’t read called Preludes to Pragmatism: Toward a Reconstruction of Philosophy (I found it in Adam Hochman’s reply to Neven Sesardic on race, discussed in my recent post “Solving Race”) which nicely sums up my stance on the issue: “There is a nondenumerable infinity of possible accurate maps we could draw for our planet; the ones we draw, and the boundaries they introduce, depend on our evolving purposes” [150]. What does this mean? It means that the Platonic idea that the philosopher’s job is to “carve nature at its joints” introduces a false teleology which is seriously misleading. If you want an equally pithy slogan for the alternative metaphysical view, try this dialethic aphorism: nature has infinite joints and no joints. What I mean by this is that, although certain sets of joints will have help us increase our store of information, knowledge and our ability to predict the future far better than others, we can’t say where the joints are really because there is no place where the joints are really because there was no designer and nature itself doesn’t carve (agents carve). To focus specifically on biology, what this means is this: there are no absolutely True Biological Categories, there is no Objective Truth about how we should taxonomise dogs and wolves, whether marsupials count as mammals, whether those skeletons found in Morocco were really homo Sapiens or proto-homo Sapiens, or whatever. There is likewise no Objective Fact about whether honey bee colonies or coral and their algae are really one organism or two, or whether (per the Gaia Hypothesis) the earth is really an organism or just a homeostatic system with feedback cycles and some policing mechanisms, or whether there are really human races or just clinally varying ethnic groups. As Godfrey-Smith apparently likes to say, ESSENTIALISM IS DEAD!
Along similar lines (and with much relevance to this ‘problem of individuality’), we should also note, as David Hume did back in 1737, that our fundamental intuitions about the persistence of macroscopic objects and living things make no empirical sense. What is the sense in which that percept of a tree your brain processed ten minutes ago was a representation of the same tree a percept of which your brain is processing now? Only that the time slice you’re ‘looking at’ now evolved directly from the one ten minutes ago. What cannot be true, no matter how we want to believe it, is that the two time slices are identical. Why can’t this be true? Because the two time slices have loads of different properties, even just according to the macroscopic or standard, anthropic descriptions (there are perceptible differences in position of leaves, in position of ants on trunk, on the specific birds nesting or roosting or resting, you know that there has been some capillary action inside the tree to transmit water, and so on and so forth). So it’s a mistake to say that “the same tree persists through time”! The two trees are not the same tree! They’re different trees! Much closer to home are those famous questions of personal identity over time. We surely want to say that the five-year-old time-slice with ‘my name’ is identical with the set of human time slices typing these words. But any two five-year-old human time-slices are going to have more properties in common than this one does with that one to which we nevertheless ‘want to say’ I am identical… And if so, how does it make any sense at all to say “I am the same person as I was when I was five”? [Hume made these observations several hundred years ago, and I defend his bundle theory here (though I don’t endorse my rejection of ‘perdurantism’ here for reasons we’ll come to): http://writingsoftclaitken.blogspot.com.au/2017/05/persistence-and-personal-identity.html]. Now, later, I’ll explain how Structural Realism helps us make sense of how this can all be true while still allowing us to say that trees and people and chairs are perfectly real and also that they do in fact perdure.  The key point is that recognising all this relativity does not at all mean we slide into some kind of weird kind of Idealism or start babbling nonsense about ‘texts’ like some kind of Pomo ninny. To understand why it doesn’t mean this means understanding Structural Realism – so that’s where we’ll turn to now.

I only very recently ‘got’ Structural Realism. After reading the book Every Thing Must Go at the beginning of 2016, the thing that most confused me – though I felt I learnt a huge amount from the book and was taken with a lot of it – was how Ladyman and Ross and the rest of the crew could simultaneously reject the ‘levels’ metaphor, and maintain that oxygen, nitrogen, trees, animals, markets and “prices” (yes, prices) were real (even if non-fundamental and ‘second-order’). This seemed to me like a contradiction. I also strongly shrinked from their Quinean-type claim that any old entity used in a scientific theory ought to be regarded as real simply if it ‘pays its rent’ in contributing to the scientific success (so to speak). This particularly irked me when it came to their discussions of economics (and I generally just disliked the fact they kept talking about economics because I am a Steve Keen fan and (as far as politics and economics go) only read post-Keynesian economists, Stiglitz, Chomsky and Peter Turchin, and consequently have been led to believe that the entire economics profession should be radically reformed (incidentally, I also constantly got this really right-wing vibe from the book, not only because of the early footnote where they randomly slag off Marx and the repetitive references to mainstream economics, but because of the constant aggression and belligerence (only ameliorated by the fact that they used ‘she’ as the default pronoun)).
It was only a couple of months ago that I suddenly understood how Ladyman and Ross could happily and consistently reject the ‘levels’ metaphor and mereology while maintaining that people, chairs, table, cats, lemurs, ants, bacteria, species, prices, markets, oxygen, nitrogen, sulfuric acid, (and so on and so forth) are all “real patterns”. The trick was being reminded of Dennett's discussions of Conway's famous Game of Life cellular automaton. Here's the takeaway:
In some sense, everything is quantum fields (or whatever). This simply has to be true. Fundamental physics is fundamental in the sense that (we’re pretty sure) it describes phenomena to the same level of accuracy in every region of the observable universe. You don’t need what Ladyman and Ross call a “locator”, or an “address” for fundamental physics; it’s fundamental because the laws of fundamental physics are universal laws, describing universal structures of reality. Hence, in some sense, everything is quantum fields. So there’s one level of reality, and it is that described by fundamental physics.
So what’s with all this other less general shit? Where does it fit in? How can you be allowed to say everything that isn't fundamental physics can nevertheless be real if you insist that there’s only one level of reality? The answer is to think about The Game of Life. Out of simple patterns in The Game of Life you see more complicated patterns ‘emerge’ – patterns which are stable and persistent and which, if you track them, allow you to compress a lot of information about the dynamics of the system. What is the analogy with the real world? Well those stable, information-compressing patterns in the Game of Life have a direct analogue: any entity that earns its keep in institutionally approved and predictively successful science basically has to be one of those stable, information-compressing patterns. So how do we decide what is real of the patterns in reality that aren't the structures directly described by fundamental physics? Well, any kind of ‘projectible’ – stable, trackable – pattern is real. And how do we determine the projectible patterns? Well, our heuristic is that any ‘entity’ that pays rent in contributing indispensably to scientific theories that achieve significant empirical success in making predictions is a real pattern. And how have we avoided multiplying the levels of reality? Because even though these patterns have a life of their own, they are still patterns in fundamental physics. You, me, that bug, jellyfish, amoebas and prices are projectible patterns in the fundamental structures of reality (as Ladyman and Ross say, this view dispenses even the need for distinguishing between types and tokens, between categories and instances; real types and real tokens are both just projectible ‘patterns’ (and so the problem of ‘species’ and the problem of ‘individuality’ really become extremely similar problems)). So there is one level of reality, and we are patterns in it. There it is!

Hopefully, it’s possible to see why this metaphysics allows us to defend a kind of ‘perdurantism’ against the extreme Humean bundle theory that I defended just before (days before) I had these insights. An individual human is a stable, persistent, projectible pattern. You can confidently track them as stable patterns, described in different contexts by different fields (economics, anthropology, psychology) but more or less stable in terms of properties, throughout their worldlines. So they are real patterns and an individual human is a really persistent pattern (a real four-dimensional worm), even if the individual time slices (of the four-dimensional worm) are not really identical.

Something like that seems true anyway. (Incidentally, I’m appreciating Ladyman and Ross’ work even more on the second reading. Every Thing Must Go really is an impressive book.)




[1] It should be noted that most of them clearly require conjunction with another one of the candidates to constitute any kind of non-circular criterion for biological individuality.

Saturday 10 June 2017

Upcoming Projects (self-motivating)

- A major project on Jackendoffian/Chomskyan semantic internalism, with reference to Russell's Theory of Descriptions, a discussion of the (disturbing) philosophy of the proposition (it's really not clear that what propositions are (I find this highly disturbing)), and a lengthy disquisition on truth (weighing up truth minimalism and Crispin Wright's form of pluralism). (Something along these lines will be my philosophy honour's thesis.)
- Part II of II of my 'Repudiating Anti-Democracy' series: a highly favourable summary of Gerry Mackie's Democracy Defended .
- A long and weighty essay on Lewis' brilliant book On the Plurality of Worlds, in which I defend the view (following Alastair Wilson) that, even though Lewis seriously undermines 'ersatzist' projects, modern physics has opened up a more plausible 'naturalisation of modality'
- Some long essay on the best 'species concepts', and Ellen Clarke's and Peter Godfrey Smith's accounts of "biological individuality", and how Structural Realism can help us understand the ontology of the macroscopic (persistent macroscopic individuals are emergent yet projectible patterns in fundamental physics, like the emergent patterns in Conway's Game of Life, and help us identify important dynamics without colossal computations)
- Two detailed recent-history timelines based on information in Michael Hudson's Killing the Host: a timeline of what happened in the White House after the GFC, and the policies that were taken; and a timeline of the relations between the EU and Greece since the crisis
- Some kind of meta-analysis of the fascinating research into plant perception and computation, as popularised in Peter Wohlleben's recent book The Hidden Life of Trees. 

Sunday 4 June 2017

Serious, lucid meta-analysis of research into sexuality and gender

http://www.thenewatlantis.com/publications/part-one-sexual-orientation-sexuality-and-gender

I'm reminded of Gore Vidal's repudiation of (at least the nominal version of the) terms "heterosexual" and "homosexual" because they are fundamentally misleading and oppressive labels.

http://www.thenewatlantis.com/publications/part-three-gender-identity-sexuality-and-gender

I'm reminded of my own writings

(Postscript, day after posting : have learned more about the authors and discovered that they have pretty fucked up views . I still maintain that it's a very careful meta-analysis. )