Search This Blog

Sunday 27 September 2015

An Essay called "Deep Moral Dilemmas and the Futility of Formalisation"

Deep Moral Dilemmas and the Futility of Formalisation

I’d like to begin this very big and ambitious essay by talking about abortion.

When it comes to the highly charged subject of abortion, I imagine that most people in the West today are basically non-absolutist pro-choicers. That is to say, I imagine most people would say that there is some kind of critical period in which it is permissible for a woman to terminate, and after that period, it is less clear that it is morally acceptable. This seems to be a reasonable claim.
Many philosophers writing about abortion like to deliberate over what the optimal moral boundary should be – whether capacity of the foetus to feel pain or consciousness or what. Often extenuating factors come in also, such as socio-economic status, age, health and whether she consented or was raped. I am not interested in exploring any of these matters. Instead, I am interested in exploring the basic beliefs people have about abortion. In carrying out this exploration, I hope to highlight the stark inconsistency of our moral intuitions on the subject. Later, this will serve a deeper argument about the problem of our moral intuitions in general. For now, though, let’s entertain a thought experiment.
Imagine, if you will, a healthy woman late in the first trimester of her pregnancy, roughly 10-12 weeks in (the start of foetushood). Suppose, if you can, that one day this woman contracts a very strange and disturbing urge. For whatever reason – be it insanity, iniquity or both – there is nothing in the world she wants more to do than scramble her foetus’ brains. We can also suppose she has three methods at her disposal. She could hire an unscrupulous and highly skilled surgeon who could use keyhole surgery to get inside the uterus, break through the weak skull and fiddle around carefully with the developing brain; she could ingest some kind of futuristic nanotechnology capsule which heads directly towards the uterus and, when on a conduit towards it, begins to release some kind of neurotoxic chemical; or she could just drink a lot of alcohol and take a lot of harmful drugs. Since her desire is not wanton malice, it is important to her that she does not do so much damage that the foetus dies. Indeed, she does want the foetus to survive to become a braindamaged baby and human. Thus, whichever method this woman opts for, we can be sure she will be careful not to take it too far.
If we assume that all of these methods of maiming result in the same level of pain to the insensate foetus – namely, zero – then I claim we must also assume that they are all morally equivalent. However, it doesn’t even matter if you don’t think, for whatever reason, that they’re all exactly equivalent methods, as long as you agree that they’re all wrong. I believe that everyone would agree that, whatever the method, the scrambling of the foetus’ brains is a profoundly immoral and possibly evil act, because it is a deliberate act of malice intending to cause grievous harm to an organism that will eventually become a human being. As a consequence of this mother’s malevolence, the child will forever be constrained, handicapped – prevented from living a full and fruitful life, or being a fully functioning member of society. It is a cruel act, and one worthy of indignation and outrage.
Next, let us imagine a typical abortion case. A healthy and capable young woman is heading into an abortion clinic during the first trimester of her pregnancy, roughly 10-12 weeks in. She is nervous but has convinced herself that she should feel no guilt. After all, she has a right to bodily autonomy, she has the right to choose.
The procedure is a success. She goes home feeling relieved and unburdened, with a heavy weight off her shoulders.
As I suggested in the introduction, in the second case most people would regard the act as morally acceptable. The woman’s rights obviously trump those of an insensate, insentient proto-human that, like the foetus in the first case, felt no pain as it was affected by external human agency. This conviction is based on our notion of inviolable human rights, particularly the idea of a human’s inalienable right to self-determination.
Yet, here’s a curious fact: in both cases the woman’s act was deliberate and premeditated. Of course, we naturally see a heavy element of malice in the former, and I had to impute a pathology to the woman to even make the case plausible. But in the former case, the foetus survived; in the latter, it did not. Given that it does not normally matter whether someone thinks their act is wrong, just that it is deliberately enacted, we must conclude that both women are responsible for their actions in the morally relevant sense. Given also that what makes the former case bad is the effect in the future, we should obviously be thinking about the future potential of the foetus in the latter case. Therefore, it could be argued that by our standard moral reasoning, we should deem both as morally repugnant. Indeed, it could be argued that we should regard the latter case as more morally repugnant, because it results in oblivion rather than mere injury. The former is removing some potential of the future child, and the latter is removing all.
Now, a pro-choicer, when confronted with this dilemma, might decide that both decisions should be morally acceptable, because – when you think about it – they both resulted in acts committed against insensate, insentient foetuses. Perhaps, therefore, we should not inculpate the woman in the former case at all; she did nothing wrong.
But this seems to me to be too violent a contradiction of our moral intuitions, and in fact obviously wrong. I believe we should not conclude that, because we don’t think the second case is bad, neither are bad. They do seem to be morally concomitant, however. So the most sensible conclusion to reach does seem to be that they are both egregious acts.
What other possible objections can one adduce to this paradox? Well, one response would be to try to further elaborate and refine the view that neither act is bad, in disaccord with my conclusion above. One could argue that we really should discount the future of the foetus in both cases, because all that matters morally is the immediate consequences on the foetus. Typically, in both intuitive morality and formal moral theories, we don’t discount future consequences, as long as they’re not too distant. For example, we would regard it as bad for someone to pollute a waterway even if it was, say, ten years before it came to be used as a resource by a community and deleterious effects were felt. Similarly, it would be morally irresponsible and borderline criminal to encourage a teenager to become addicted to smoking even if it was many years before the habit manifested in noticeably harmful effects on his health. Nevertheless, you might claim that there is a morally relevant difference between harm inflicted against insensate, insentient foetuses and harm inflicted against already living humans (even if there’s a delay on when the “harm” actually occurs in both cases).
Then again, if you’re suppressing one’s essentialist moral intuitions enough not to set an absolute threshold on abortion or to believe in some kind of fixed “ensoulment”, why wouldn’t you suppress them in dealing with this problem? The question is, is there a super-intuitive reason why my other examples of wrong acts with a delayed harm are different from the cases involving a foetus? I don’t think so. Just as you might say you can’t inflict immediate harm on an insensate, insentient foetus, you can’t inflict immediate harm on a person by polluting a lake they will drink from in ten years, or by encouraging them to start a habit that will give them lung cancer in fifty. However, the latter two cases obviously are morally wrong, because they still do inflict harm, just at a delay. Therefore, based on the previous conclusions reached, I submit that this objection also fails. To codify the refutation of the objection:
1.)    Even if you don’t want to say the first case would have an immediate bad effect, we agreed that damaging the brain of an insensate, insentient foetus had some kind of future deleterious effect, handicapping the future child
2.)    There is no logical way of arguing that that act is morally worse than a healthy and capable woman terminating a similar foetus completely, because ending life must trump scrambling brains   
3.)    We typically regard acts that inflict harm at a delay as very bad despite the delay
Therefore, we should still conclude that in both cases, the woman commits an egregious act.
A pro-choicer will be very unhappy with this conclusion, so let us try some other possible attacks on the paradox. Another attempt at resolving it in favour of the pro-choicers would involve implementing what I will call a consequentialist survival model. Contra what I said earlier, one could argue that the two cases are not morally concomitant, because when a woman, even a healthy woman, aborts a foetus, there is no guarantee that, if she hadn’t, the foetus would survive to become a fully-fledged human being. By contrast, if she doesn’t abort it and instead injures it, and it then survives, she has done harm to an organism that is now an infant. On this view, if a woman just like the one in the first case injured her baby and it didn’t survive, then she would not be culpable and the act of injuring would not be wrong. The essential measure here is survival.
In my opinion, this model is weak for two reasons. The first is that, while there’s no guarantee that a foetus in a healthy woman would survive to become a fully-fledged human being, the probability of its anthropomorphosis is not so low that we would, in other moral situations, regard it as permissible. To wit, if there was even a 20% chance that your sick and temporarily insentient grandmother was going to live to once again be healthy, you would not want anyone killing her pre-emptively on the likelihood that she might not. And when we’re discussing foetuses in healthy mothers, the probabilities of survival are much higher than 20%.
The second is the related riposte that this model requires such an extreme strain of consequentialism that not even a self-professed consequentialist would abide it under normal circumstances. Intentions are entirely out the window under this extreme consequentialist model. The very strange implication of this is that it becomes totally repugnant if a foetus is injured through malice and survives, but totally morally acceptable if the foetus is sent into oblivion, even if its existence is also ended through overreaching malice.
Of course, one could argue that neither of these rebuttals to this moral model are actually good, because they are essentially just restatements of the paradox. This would mean that the model actually has the right implications, because it gives some kind of formal justification for the paradox.  My first rebuttal relies on the premise that extreme consequentialism must be wrong, but the moral model assumes that extreme consequentialism is right when one is talking about abortion. So I’m not properly engaging with the meta-ethical assumption. My second rebuttal is basically just saying “The model is weak because the implications are the same strange ones we noted at the start via the thought experiments”. When you think about it, this is also only right, since the point of the model is to defend the strange implications!
And here we reach a fork in the road. We could say that using an extreme consequentialist model to defend the moral difference between the two cases is prima facie wrong, and accept that there is a very good case against late first trimester abortions. Any adoptee of this stance would presumably lower his or her threshold of abortion permissibility, because the relevant index would have switched from consciousness or sensation to foetushood itself. Alternatively, we could say that we should use an extreme consequentialist model to defend the moral difference between the two cases, and therefore resign oneself moral inconsistency, because you couldn’t possibly be such an extreme consequentialist all the time. Which fork should you take?
I am going to defer judgement on that question for the moment, and instead take an excursion into the history of secular moral thought. By the end, we may have a better vantage point to view it from.

  Ever since the Humanitarian Revolution of the Enlightenment, civilised morality has progressed with two major, corollary trends: it has moved away from essentialism, and it has become increasingly reliant on reason over gospel. Since time immemorial, Christians have cherrypicked the Biblical passages that seem most felicitous to them and entirely overlooked the many tenets and parables that seem wrong or aberrant. The Bible is such a diverse and heterogeneous tome that even if you do try to set up an absolutely pious, pure society founded on its guidelines, like the Puritans or the Westboro Baptists, you necessarily fail, and end up rejecting certain tenets. The Westboro Baptists, for example, seem – generally speaking – to prefer the Old to the New Testament (while also hating Jews, despite that group being the authors of the Old Testament).
Yet, in the Enlightenment, philosophers began to think about morality with a far more secular frame of mind than they had once done, moving away from theology altogether. Although many still drew assistance from the Bible with a core of secular reasoning, or drew directly from the Bible with a pretence of secular reasoning, some brave souls tried to put aside the Bible altogether. Many of the thinkers in this revolutionary era began trying to deduce what is right and what is wrong from “first principles”, with the founding assumption that morality might turn out to be much like the revolution that was Newtonian physics. In the 17th Century, for example, John Locke controverted the prevailing assumptions of his day by elevating women above the status of property in the Second Treatise of Government, and suggesting they be both granted the right to look after the home in the absence of a man and the capacity to leave the compact of marriage themselves. Just like his entire political theory, this affirmation of (some of) the rights of women was a product of thinking about morality secularly, without allowing the dirty sediment of religion to muddy the waters – at least not so directly as had been done in the past.
In the 18th Century, the secularisation of morality took a huge leap forward as there arose many thinkers engaged in the enterprise of establishing a morality wholly independent of the gospel. Immanuel Kant is probably the most famous of these. Kant attempted to formulate a Rationalist doctrine of morality from reason alone, and thereby claimed to have identified the true, ineluctable principles of morality. Admittedly, these principles roughly supported the Ten Commandments, but they were not worded like any moral laws in the Bible and Kant was sure to exclude religious dogma from their deduction. Though now regarded as highly flawed, Kant’s grandiose moral labours would have a massive influence on moral thought for the next few centuries, and even continue to exercise philosophers today. Around the same time in the late 18th Century, Mary Wollstonecraft was writing a book that what would later be regarded as perhaps the greatest feminist polemic of all time, A Vindication of the Rights of Women. In this magnum opus, she famously proclaimed that women were not at all inferior to men. Given the Bible does suggest numerous times, both explicitly and implicitly, that women are inferior to men,[1] this was obviously a highly blasphemous stance. Most importantly, it epitomised the secular spirit of the age: the willingness of thinkers in the Enlightenment to privilege the inviolable principles of pure reason over ancient religious dogma. Because of thinkers like Kant and Wollstonecraft, by the turn of the 19th Century, morality was no longer the province of a holy book and its public spokesmen; it had become a matter of reason. The age of secular morality had begun. Slavery would be its first victim.
As everyone knows, the onset of the Industrial Revolution brought with it massive social upheavals, and would eventually further propel the moral advance. Although the rights of women were barely advanced in the 19th Century, there were some notable moral movements of other kinds. Fascinatingly, they were in large part fostered by righteous, passionate fiction writers seeking to nurture empathy for excluded or reviled groups. Harriet Beecher Stowe’s bestselling 1852 novel Uncle Tom’s Cabin is known to have had an enormous impact on the American abolitionist movement, while Dickens novels like Oliver Twist, Nicholas Nickleby, David Copperfield, Bleak House, and Great Expectations achieved enormous success in entreating their readers to ponder the social stratification, injustice, cruelty and absurdity of British society, and the plight of the working-class, particularly children. Never before had so many upper-class aristocrats been made to ponder their privilege and the humanity they shared with the millions of unwashed ruffians below them. In his book The Better Angels of our Nature, Steven Pinker follows most of the historians of the period in adducing this explosion of polemical literature as one of the main exogenous causes of the shift in the zeitgeist and expansion of the moral circle.
With the arrival of the first wave of the feminist movement and its vociferous campaign for female suffrage, this quest to advance moral thought through pure reason redoubled. Within decades, women across the civilised world had obtained the right to vote. Then, in the 1950s and 1960s, the civil rights movement began to gain momentum. Black activists proclaimed that they were as human as whites and should no longer be forced to suffer discrimination. By the late 1960s, after the work of such heroic figures as Martin Luther King had begun to uproot entrenched racist attitudes, legal discrimination against blacks had ended across the civilised world.
As soon as the civil rights movement had run its course, the second wave of the feminist movement began to surge forward, using civil rights as its model. Within only a few years, feminists had achieved massive gains in legislation and quantifiable changes in attitudes, leading to an immense expansion of female opportunities and autonomy, and a revolutionary liberation from patriarchal control. The gay rights movement followed soon after, eventually winning for itself the total legalisation of homosexuality and an increasing acceptance of homosexual practices. This has culminated in the phenomenally high levels of gay tolerance that we enjoy in the West today.
The animal rights movement also began to pick up during this period, although it is important to note that, like female liberation, its seeds had been sown back during the Enlightenment. Just as Mary Wollstonecraft rejected the reasons why women were thought to be inferior to men, the 18th Century utilitarian humanist, Jeremy Bentham, is famous for having remarked, “The question is not, “Can they reason?” nor, “Can they talk?” but “Can they suffer?”” In the 1970s and 80s, animal activists began to use such arguments to encourage people to expand the recently expanded moral circle of the West yet further – not just within our species, but beyond it. The movement to invest animals with rights and end their suffering and slaughter rapidly amassed an ardent following. As a result of this movement, vegetarianism went from totally unthinkable for any sane human being to merely radical, and rates of vegetarianism in the West continue to increase (bumpily) to this day.
One is liable to forget just how many dramatic moral leaps have been made over the last centuries, and how much the world has changed in the moral concatenation of the decades since the 1950s. As Pinker argues, people constantly fail to see how much more permissive and tolerant our norms are, and how much better than the past the world we live in now is. The truth is that the expansiveness of the moral norms we in the West have now is utterly aberrant: it is historically unprecedented, and it is unparalleled in any human society ever documented. Collectively speaking (and the internet notwithstanding), us 21st Century Western citizens are astronomically more pacifistic, empathetic, soppy, mawkish, softcocked, sissyish and abstemious than any other human beings that have ever lived. The rates of violence and tolerance of violence in our societies right now are infinitesimal compared to those of every other society ever documented.
When you think about the evolution of morality, the fact that highly peaceful, tolerant modern Western societies are anomalous is hardly surprising. After all, human morality is fundamentally built on only two selectional mechanisms: kin altruism and reciprocal altruism. These manifest themselves in our myriad moral emotions, such as sympathy, compassion, admiration, honour and sense of justice, along with guilt, shame, anger, indignation, disapprobation and vengefulness. They also manifest themselves in norms and taboos that vary from society to society, circumscribed only by the human emotional palette. While I earlier suggested that one of the main developments in secular morality was the shift away from religion and gospel, in truth, the deeper shift of the Humanitarian Revolution and the rights movements of the 20th Century was away from our primal moral intuitions, and towards cerebration and reasoning. The Bible is itself merely a bricolage of ancient moral attitudes, so it is no surprise that it features advocacy of massacres and rapes in war, a recurring abasement of women to mere “chattel” (along with its general endorsement of patriarchy) and a general discord with modern, progressive moral beliefs about just about anything (slaves, homosexuals, animals). As with most primitive people, the authors of the Bible extended empathy only to a limited circle and only in certain circumstances, and moral rules were always contingent (none of the Ten Commandments were meant to apply to foreign peoples, for example). A certain essentialism was also a given. All women were regarded as the same and thought of as deserving the same, oppressive treatment, despite women being as varied and diverse a group of individuals as men, and including people who are innately closer to the average of the opposite gender than the average of their own. All foreigners were regarded as one homogenous group, typically with certain animalistic, wicked, demonic or repulsive traits – an essentialist attitude that enabled the complete erasure of empathy in warfare and the resultant pillaging, depredation and rape. All animals were regarded as fundamentally inferior on a very deep level and therefore could be abused or killed with total impunity.  
Importantly, these kinds of barbaric attitudes towards people outside the in-group are more in tune with the predictions of evolutionary psychology than any of our moral beliefs. It would be suicide in the wild for an animal to extend its empathy to human beings outside of its kin or to any party unlikely to have any chance of future reciprocation. Yet it is precisely this that our humanistic norms, slowly built up over hundreds of years, encourage us to do.
So despite the primal impulses to the contrary, us contemporary humans have managed to extend our empathy way beyond our kin and way beyond those who might reward us for our concern. Most of us abjure all violence against other humans, abhor prejudice and discrimination against all races, creeds and classes, revile war as a great moral evil that we must do everything in our power to avoid, and some of us even refrain from eating animals. Every single one of these moral stances would be quite literally inconceivable to a hunter-gatherer.

(And now we return to abortion).

In primitive societies, there is extensive documented evidence of infanticide. You might intuit that this could have interesting implications for abortion. Perhaps before inculcation into our Christian-dominated social norms, we should naturally incline towards an insouciant attitude towards abortion. However, I don’t think this is quite true, and for a few reasons.
Firstly, while the existence of a behaviour in many human cultures is a good indication that the behaviour is an innate instinct, it doesn’t guarantee it.
Secondly, abortion is not actually infanticide (defined as killing after birth), and primitive societies certainly don’t practise abortion widely. One might think that this would be irrelevant because infanticide is basically like a worse version of abortion, meaning that abortion and infanticide should go together morally. But this is not how human psychology works: even if abortion is logically a kind of not-really-infanticide that isn’t as bad, the fact that infanticide and abortion play out very differently makes them very emotionally different, too.
Thirdly, in all the cultures in which it is documented, infanticide is not practised wantonly, but with specific motivations that make sense in terms of evolutionary psychology. Babies are killed if they are deformed or dopey; mothers kill their babies if they think they cannot support them sufficiently or would be foolish to do so with other healthy offspring around; and men murder any previous children raised by the woman they are shacking up with. For a primitive person to abort a foetus would be rare because there would be few motivations to compensate for the great dangers that would presumably be involved. For a mother to get someone to perform some sort of improvised, dangerous abortion on her, she must be willing to risk her future reproductive potential and possibly her life. She would not risk those things on the off chance that her foetus was deformed, and she would not risk those things on the possibility that her future child will not be healthy and hardy enough to invest in. A man would also be unlikely to violently force a woman to abort a baby even if he was sure that baby was not his, because he could injure or kill the woman, and it would not be in his interests to do that.
The fourth and most important reason why it doesn’t make much sense to say that we might incline towards a permissive stance on abortion is that the central pillar of pro-lifeism, the notion of the soul, is itself an intuition of innate human psychology. The quintessential essentialist attitude is that all human beings have an essence which distinguishes us from all the other animals, and endows us with all the fundamental human traits. Thus, belief in the soul is a profoundly primitive conviction.
So it seems to me that pro-choice as a position probably relies slightly more on the denial of intuition than pro-life. Like most contemporary Westerners, I believe that pro-choicers rightly dismiss the essentialist, pro-life attitude towards abortion as superstitious, unscientific nonsense, just as philosophers have been arguing for centuries that all essentialist attitudes towards out-groups are superstitious, unscientific nonsense.
Yet, here’s where we return to our dilemma. The paradox raised by the comparison of the two thought experiments was highly useful for illustrating how some kinds of primal moral intuitions still infect our moral reasoning, even when we discard essentialist thinking. Indeed, the application of modern science to morality has really opened up a Pandora’s Box of dilemmas that pose such deep problems to our moral reasoning that people prefer to pretend they don’t exist. Despite what some may like to think, everyone’s morality is still underpinned by numerous essentialist beliefs and assumptions, and science has only complicated the picture. Every reasonable person in the West agrees that it would be best for our morality to be as rational, logical and scientific as possible, so we do allow scientific knowledge to enter the mix – but only with massive constraints. What do I mean by that? Well, here are three examples of monolithic essentialisms that pervade the supposedly well-reasoned and anti-superstitious moral beliefs of us Westerners:
1.)    People are fully rational, autonomous agents fully responsible for their actions
This essentialist claim basically undergirds the entire criminal justice system and much of our intuitive morality, yet you have to define “rational”, “autonomous” and “responsible” in very peculiar ways to even attempt to reconcile this essentialism with modern neuroscience and cognitive psychology. Rationality is pretty much impossible to define scientifically. If you take “optimal rationality” in the way a layman would, to mean something like “Always making decisions based on reasoned deliberation and solid inferences”, it’s fair to say that the average human is light years distant from the ideal. Reasoned deliberation and solid inferences are used in science, but human beings in the real world tend to use heuristics, best-guesses and act on impulse. Meanwhile, autonomy is, scientifically speaking, very close to meaningless. Autonomy is basically synonymous with free will, and no neuroscientist thinks that our most pure conception of this notion fits with our picture of the brain. Indeed, as all philosophers know, our deep attachment to these two words, autonomy and free-will, clashes violently with modern science and raises some very deep questions. How can you really apply the dictionary definition of this word “autonomy” to any human being when none of us have any choice over what genes we are born with, how our brains are wired into the uterus, how we come out of the birth canal, what environment we are raised in, what our parents are like, where we go to school, who we interact with, etc? How can we say we have free will when our brains are merely highly sophisticated computational systems that operate almost entirely under the cover of darkness, with most of the machinations occurring totally beneath our awareness? How can we say we are self-determined when the impression everyone has of being a kind of executive or concertmaster over their mind and body is totally illusory? How can we say that we are autonomous beings when it there is no one real “self” but only a brain composed of a series of highly complex intricate electrical networks arranged into highly complex interacting modules? And this brings us to responsibility. Are we responsible? Probably not – at least not on any normal definition.
2.)    All human beings are sacred. The fact that we even have “human rights” suggests that we have wacko superstitious beliefs about ourselves. After all, what are “rights” from a physicist’s perspective? (Put it this way, they’re not quarks.) Clearly, we invented the notion of rights to make legislating morality easier, using the same logic as the fictions of rationality, autonomy and responsibility, which, as I said, are necessary to undergird prosecution and punishment. Nevertheless, isn’t it completely insane that we don’t accept killing a severely disabled baby or a demented, vegetated old person with sophisticated methods that would cause no pain, but we totally accept killing animals that are more sentient and possibly more sensate with far more macabre and traumatic methods? Literally the only reason people can adduce to defend this discrepancy is the sanctity of life, and that isn’t even a reason. I mean, you would think this is code for “soul” if it weren’t for the fact that irreligious people use it a hell of a lot. In fact, it is a kind of proxy for the soul, but one that makes even less sense, because, unlike the soul, a general “sanctity” doesn’t have any kind of referent. The soul at least resides somewhere in the noumenal realm or something. Sanctity, by contrast, is pure poetry. Basically, if you think about the logic behind most people’s uses of the phrase, you conclude that if they were fully honest they’d have to replace the phrase with the following: “I don’t know what the “sanctity of life” means but I feel it is significant and it seems to solve the logical conundrum of our speciesism. If we don’t have this phrase to rely on, I can’t justify my strong moral prioritisation of the lives of humans over the lives of other animals. I therefore need this essentialism to preserve my moral beliefs.” Now, I do not mean to suggest that we should totally dispense with the idea of human sanctity, because the truth is that we do actually need the belief. If we did truly carry out Jeremy Bentham’s dream and simplified our norm of wrongdoing to all acts that cause suffering, we could not cope. To truly end any prioritisation of human beings over other sensate animals would quite literally extend our moral circle beyond its logical limits. We could not hope to actually implement a morality where every sensate creature was equally worthy of moral concern as humans, and any attempt would probably soon be self-defeating.
3.)    Family members and kin are more deserving of affection, compassion and charity than strangers and nobodies. Can you imagine trying to treat every single human being equally? Can you imagine being a parent and refusing to prioritise the feelings, wants and needs of your children over any other person’s? Can you imagine going to  a nursing home at which your grandparents reside and chatting to every single geriatric without fail, allocating the same 3 minutes and 30 seconds of attention and affection to each, including your own? Obviously, it would be impossible to actually implement anything even remotely close to a literal moral impartiality. But let’s say you made the minimum number of compromises of impartiality necessary to still live a relatively normal and fruitful life. Imagine being a parent trying to do this. Thinking about it rapidly becomes utterly absurd. There is no one abstemious and emotionally repressive enough in the entire world to even get close to any kind of impartial moral ideal. It is quite clear that any greater-than-half-hearted attempt to treat strangers and non-kin the same as family and kin would just not be humanly possible. Yet, importantly, there can be no good logical justification for our massive bias towards family and kin (only an evolutionary explanation for it). All it is is a base instinct, not a well-reasoned preference.  
It should be clear by now that even in this advanced state of moral development, when reason has been entrenched as the default method of moral arbitration for centuries, our moral beliefs are still hopelessly reliant on primal, essentialist intuitions. So what should we do?
If you want my answer – nothing. I am firmly of the view that we should not try to fight these intuitions to the death, because the true extermination of our essentialist moral intuitions would mean the near-total obliteration of human nature itself, and certainly the extirpation of morality. Instead, we should resign ourselves to our fate: morality is not a science, it cannot be formalised and we are forever doomed to be logically inconsistent when applying it. It is a bleak claim, but it is the truth.
I am now finally in the position to judge which fork one should take in response to the paradox I set up all those pages ago. Now is the time when all must be revealed. And the answer is…
Neither!
It saddens me to say it, but the truth is that I tricked you. To me, neither of the forks are quite acceptable. I believe the best one would probably be a third, subtler sidetrack that I never mentioned before – one that is not quite the second, but branches off slightly from it.
Contra the first fork, I submit that the apparent clash of the intuitions is ultimately immaterial. The reason I believe this is that such a clash is not anomalous in contemporary, secular morality. Indeed, we should be used to our morality being riddled with inconsistencies. As I have argued, that has increasingly become the nature of the beast since we abandoned the moral certitude of the Church and started to question our primal intuitions.
But why is the second fork – to accept an extreme consequentialist model that only need apply to abortion – not quite ideal either? It is not quite ideal, in my view, because it is an unnecessary complication of a problem that isn’t really resolved just by bandying around fancy philosophical terms.
So what is this magical third fork then? Well, to be honest, it’s rather anti-climactic. The third fork available to one confronting such a dilemma is basically to shrug the entire thing off and say the following: “It is true that our moral intuitions seem to be contradicting each other here, but at least believing that there is some kind of difference between an early foetus and a human being is better than believing that there is none because of an imaginary thing called a “soul”. Any kind of attempt to constrain the most hard-line essentialism in morality has got to be a good thing, because it brings morality closer to reason and truth, and this is worth the cost of seeding moral reasoning with more blatant inconsistencies. A mixture of essentialism and science is always better than pure essentialism, even if the mix is very dirty.”
Surely, this is our only real option.


[Credit to H. Ramage for steering me back on course]









[1] Eve is created from rib-bone, for example.

No comments:

Post a Comment