Search This Blog

Friday 28 October 2016

AN ESSAY ON THE MYSTERIES OF THE MIND

Take Home Exercise for Philosophy of Mind and Cognition
(b)Critically evaluate the arguments for the Language of Thought and/or the Map Theory

In this essay, I examine the arguments for the several stances it is possible to take in the ‘debate’ (largely implicit) between the Language of Thought Hypothesis and the Map Theory of cognition. My ultimate conclusion is that, whilst so many fundamental issues are still extraordinarily unclear, there is one particular intermediate stance in this debate that has significantly more weight behind it than any other.
I first discuss how, for both hard-line connectionists (those who think that the brain undergoes no ‘classical computation’) and hard-line Fodorians (those who think the key parts of cognition will be explained only by classical computational models), the stakes between the “Language of Thought Hypothesis” and “Map Theory” of cognition are quite clear: if the LoTH is the right theory of all cognition, then the hard-line connectionists are completely wrong, and if complex cognition occurs without any real LoT, then the adherents of Fodor’s computational-representational theory are completely wrong. I argue that both these poles are probably wrong, but that the connectionist extreme is much less implausible than the Fodorian one. I secondly explore the intricate intermediate position that that all (or nearly all) cognition in non-human animals involves connectionist ‘software’, captured by “Map Theory”, and yet that the Language of Thought theory represents a classical ‘program’ run only by humans. This thesis has not been actually expounded in any literature I am aware of, although it seems to me to be the hypothesis that has the most weight behind it of all. As I argue, it is highly concordant with Noam Chomsky’s carefully considered hypothesis (since the mid-1990s) for the origin of the human language faculty/explanation for the “Great Leap Forward”; the notion that productive thought is bound up with productive language is supported by evidence from developmental psychology; the notion that the vast majority of biological ‘software’ is connectionist is strengthened by well-known considerations about the ‘hardware’ of the brain and the nature of evolution; and finally, despite Fodor’s many protestations, it seems to me that Prototype Theory is the best account of the nature of our concepts, and Prototype-structured concepts are better explained in terms of “Map Theory” than the “Language of Thought”.

In The Philosophy of Mind and Cognition, Frank Jackson and David Braddon-Mitchell are careful not to hitch the Map Theory to the connectionist programme in AI, or the Language of Thought to more ‘classical models of cognition’. They note that the truth is much more complex and that it may often be unclear whether a ‘classical’ program is being implemented in a connectionist substrate (indeed, they claim that there might be no “source code” for the brain at all) [Braddon-Mitchell & Jackson, 2007: 219]. Nevertheless, they do suggest a certain harmony between connectionism and the “Map Theory”, and between classical computation and Fodor’s LoT. This makes perfect sense, because a hard-line connectionist cannot possibly accept the LoTH, and the Map Theory is explicitly proposed as the one alternative to the LoTH.
Paul and Patricia Churchland, the influential reductive neuro-computationalists, are probably the most prominent proponents of what I’ve called ‘hard-line’ connectionism. For several decades, the central philosophical claim of these two neuro-philosophers has been that classical cognitive science is (and always has been) on the wrong track, because the brain’s hardware is connectionist[1] and we can only understand the brain’s ‘software’ by investigating the nature of the hardware, rather than constructing abstract, simple models of rules and representations which may have no “psychological reality”. In numerous articles and papers from the late 80s onwards, the Churchlands have argued that evidence from neurobiology[2] makes it clear that the Language of Thought (which they tend to lump together with ‘Folk Psychology’ as part of the one Fodorian package), even if apparently explanatory, simply doesn’t exist [P.S. Churchland, 1986; P.M. Churchland, 1989; P.S. & P.M. Churchland, 1990; P.S. Churchland & Sejnowski, 1990].
It is crucial to point out, of course, that there was always a key weakness in the Churchlands’ critiques of classical cognitive science and the LoTH – a weakness that would ultimately allow Fodor to evade their attacks without working up too much of a sweat at all. This key weakness was that the Churchlands didn’t attempt to provide a serious alternative, connectionist-based theory of thought (as opposed to mere detailed accounts of bio-chemical processes correlated to certain kinds of cognition) to the one they so roundly rejected. The absence of such a theory in the Churchlandian canon meant that it remained justified for Fodor to simply repeat the famous remark he made in his seminal 1975 work: that the LoTH is “the only game in town” [1975: 406]. And as Fodor and Pylyshyn pointed out in their influential 1988 critique of connectionism (which includes extensive reference to the Churchlands), without such an alternative account of the actual nature of thought, the neurobiological evidence marshalled in supposed contradiction of the LoTH cannot nullify the abductive argument, because the neurobiological details do not in themselves itself constitute an explanatory science of the mind [Fodor & Pylyshyn, 1988]. As Fodor and Pylyshyn emphasise in this same article, no connectionist can explain productivity and systematicity except by creating “Classical architecture” in connectionist models, yet these are the two key features of thought that form the basis of Fodor’s argument to begin with [Fodor & Pylyshyn, 1988: 33-40].
Fortunately for the connectionists, however, Frank Jackson and David Braddon-Mitchell’s “Map Theory” does provide such an alternative account of the ultimate nature of thought. Evidently, if such a theory is at all tenable, it lends significant credence to the hard-line connectionists, because the very fact of its existence destroys Fodor’s key abductive argument. And unfortunately for Fodor, it does indeed seem to me that the Map Theory is plausible as an alternative theory of thought – in fact, highly plausible. The idea of thought as involving highly structured, non-sentential, ‘nth’-dimensional map-like representations actually possesses a number of virtues over the LoTH: it is (at least intuitively) much more neatly reconcilable with connectionist networks and the ‘hardware’ of the brain, since a map is an inherently ‘distributed’ structure; it gives a far more plausible account than the LoTH of how it is that our beliefs about people, places and events can so fluidly change as we have new experiences and take in new information (our mental ‘maps’ are simply updated); it seems to explain memory and memory-retrieval in a much more plausible way than a Language of Thought, since it is not necessary to claim that we have a vast number of propositions stored in our memory which we can retrieve at will; it would appear to explain certain weaknesses we have in formal reasoning (for example, why content seems to matter to our ability to carry out tasks of reasoning with formally identical structure [Jackson, Braddon-Mitchell, 2007: 235]); it appears to have evolutionary considerations in its favour over the LoTH, since a Language of Thought is a highly elegant computational system which seems at odds with the haphazard makeshift nature of evolution (it seems unlikely that a LoT would be the kind of system to slowly crystallise, and it seems highly unlikely that our ancient Cambrian ancestors had a Language of Thought, whereas they might have had primitive ‘map-like’ representations); and it can account (seemingly) for “systematicity”, since the ‘places’ in the cognitive maps can be switched. All in all, therefore, the Churchlandian position is, in my view, massively strengthened by the “Map Theory”.
With that said, of course, the reason that I do not think that the hard-line connectionist position is likely to be right is that the Map Theory, even if it does seem to account for systematicity, it doesn’t quite answer Fodor’s productivity criterion. As a result, it cannot explain the apparent infinite generative capacity of human cognition – our ability to think an infinite array of discrete thoughts by finite (combinatorial) means. As I am about to suggest, however, it may very well be that only humans have this full-strength productivity. This would imply that the Map Theory might be a far more general account of biological cognition, and that the hard-line connectionist position might be the correct one for all creatures on Earth except us. As I’m about to argue, I think this is actually the most plausible stance of all.
Perhaps the major consideration in support of the view that only Homo sapiens has a LoT in Fodor’s sense (with a combinatorial syntax which allows for infinite productivity) is that it accords with Chomsky’s hypothesis about the evolution of the language faculty. Whilst undoubtedly a highly controversial hypothesis – disputed even by other notable generativists (for example, Ray Jackendoff and Steven Pinker [2005]) – the conjecture does have nontrivial theoretical and empirical backing.
Chomsky largely eschewed speculation about the evolution of the language faculty for the first few decades of the Universal Grammar research programme, but he has become quite vocal in espousing his ‘spandrelist’ hypothesis about the evolution of the “Faculty of Language” ever since he wrote The Minimalist Program in 1995. The central idea of Chomsky’s “Minimalist Program” is that it is possible to distil the ‘Universal Grammar’ into one basic computational operation called “Merge”, with two forms, “External” (for separate objects A and B) and “Internal” (for two objects where at least one object contains the other) [Chomsky, 1995]. This lends credence to this spandrelist hypothesis because of the elegant computational simplicity of such a system (“like a snowflake”), and the fact that this computational procedure subserves thought as fundamentally (or more fundamentally) as it subserves language.
The most rigorous defence of this evolutionary hypothesis appeared only recently, in a 2015 book Chomsky co-authored with the MIT computer scientist, Robert Berwick, entitled Why Only Us? : Language and Evolution. In this short work, Chomsky and Berwick specifically defend the thesis that this “Merge” operation first originated by a single mutation in a human individual around 80,000-100,000 years ago, which gave rise to recursion and hierarchical structure in that individual’s thoughts [Chomsky & Berwick, 2015]. Whilst they don’t invoke Fodor explicitly, it is clear that they see this as the moment the “productivity” property key to Fodor’s LoT actually emerged (for the first time in the history of life on the planet). They hold that this capacity would have had some selectional advantage, and would have spread throughout the population before being secondarily externalised [Chomsky & Berwick, 2015]. Much of the book is taken up by arguments in defence of an anti-adaptationist, ‘messy’ view of evolution as involving “stochastic effects” and both gradual and sudden developments, with more at work than simple natural selection in simple genetically varied populations. However, there are also a number of positive considerations adduced in favour of the hypothesis, many of them (in my view) highly compelling.
Firstly, recursion appears to be a property that is either absolutely present or absolutely absent, so seemingly couldn’t come about as a gradual adaptation [72]. Secondly, there is strong evidence (disputed by some) that no other species on the planet is capable of recursive communication – birdsong, they claim, never gets further than “linear chunking” or iteration of “motifs” [142]. Thirdly, the fact that human linguistic externalisation is modality-independent (sign language has the same level of syntactic complexity as spoken language, and is learnt as rapidly by children in the right environment) seems to constitute good evidence that the Faculty of Language was first a Faculty of Thought [74]. Fourthly, the sudden emergence of productivity around 80,000 years ago appears to be one of the best possible explanations for what Jarred Diamond famously called the “Great Leap Forward” [37]. Fifthly, the extent of language variation in the world can seemingly explained by the fact that the means of externalisation did not actually co-evolve with the core computational system, but are instead much more ancient systems being co-opted for the task [82]. Sixthly, the evolutionary timeframe of the change is certainly not ruled out by the reconstructed genomic evidence used to compare Homo sapiens with its ancestors and cousins [Chapter 4]. And, finally, there is a neuro-anatomical hypothesis for what actually happened to create the key “Merge” mutation – the dorsal and ventral “fiber tracts” linking different language-related areas of the brain formed a ring (which does not exist in birds) [Chapter 3].
There is also evidence from developmental psychology that lends support to the idea that language is bound up with a special form of thought that marks humans out as unique (and this naturally holds even if Chomsky and Berwick’s hypothesis is a fair way off the mark in terms of timeframe and suddenness of evolution). As Antoni Gomila notes in a critical review of Jerry Fodor’s 2008 book The Language of Thought Revisited, “there is no evidence for the systematicity and productivity of thought before the development of language, at the end of the second year” [Gomila, 2011: 151]. Gomila cites the child psychologist Elizabeth Spelke for this claim, whose experiments suggest that babies are born with modular packets of knowledge of particular contents (physical, numerical, biological, intentional), but that such knowledge does not admit of productive combination before language – instead it is context-dependent and encapsulated [Spelke, 2003]. It seems that the role of language in development is to create interaction between these different modules.
Another major virtue of this idea that the LoT is human-specific is that it means we can still maintain the benefits of a largely connectionist view of biological cognition (those benefits espoused by the Churchlands, in particular, general biological plausibility (in terms of physiology and evolution)), and the advantages of Map Theory as a general account of biological cognition. It only means that we have to say that humans may be the only species with a ‘classical program’.
Finally, adopting the Map Theory as an account of the majority of human thought also seems to work far better for explaining the fuzzy nature of human concepts, described by “Prototype Theory” in cognitive linguistics – the research programme pioneered by Eleanor Rosch’s studies about ‘categories’ in the 1970s. Map Theory would seem to suggest that concepts are not discretely structured, but form part of wider cognitive architectures. If one accepts the tight connection between connectionist software and Map Theory, then there is certainly reason to think that Map Theory is highly compatible with Prototype Theory since, as Gomila notes, connectionist models which are based on Prototype Theory have met with increasing success since the 1990s [2011: 149].
   
Overall, I think that the debate between Fodor’s Language of Thought Hypothesis and the “Map Theory” of cognition raise deep and interesting questions about the nature of the mind which are not currently soluble – although some possibilities seem distinctly more likely than others. I think that the LoTH is extremely unlikely to be a true theory of all cognition, and thus that the ‘hard-line’ Fodorians are seriously misled. I think that the Map Theory, most naturally joined with connectionist models, is far less implausible as a general account of the cognitive architecture of biological creatures – however I think it fails to account for productivity in humans. These considerations have ultimately led me to the view that the most likely hypothesis is that Homo sapiens is the only species to possess a Language of Thought, implemented as a ‘classical program’ on top of the connectionist hardware and software that all biological organisms probably possess.
Naturally, I acknowledge that this claim, despite the justifications I have given for it, is still an extremely speculative one. I am also aware that I have an aesthetic bias for this view: I think it is a beautiful notion that humans might be the only creature with a classical program that was key for our success in colonising the planet and reaching civilisation… So it might be totally wrong.





























Reference List

Braddon-Mitchell, D and Jackson, F. (2007), The Philosophy of Mind and Cognition, 2nd edition, Blackwell Publishing.

Chomsky, N. (1995), The Minimalist Program, The MIT Press, Cambridge, M.A.

Chomsky, N & Berwick, R. (2015), Why Only Us? : Language and Evolution, The MIT Press, Cambridge, M.A.

Churchland, P.M. (1989), A Neurocomputational Perspective: The Nature of Mind and the Structure of Science, The MIT Press, Cambridge, M.A.

Churchland, P.M. and P.S. (1990), Could a machine think? Scientific American 262 (1):32-37.

Churchland, P.S.  (1986), Neurophilosophy: Towards a Unified Science of Mind-Brain, The MIT Press, Cambridge, M.A.

Churchland, P.S and Sejnowski, T. (1990), “Neural representation and neural computation”, Philosophical Perspectives 4:343-382.

Fodor, J. (1975), The Language of Thought, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, M.A.

Fodor, J and Pylyshyn Z. (1988), “Connectionism and Cognitive Architecture: A Critical Analysis”, Cognition 28 (1-2):3-71.

Gomila, A. (2011), “The Language of Thought: Still a Game in Town?” Teorema: Revista Internacional De FilosofĂ­a, 30(1), 145-155.

Jackendoff, P and Pinker, S. (2005), “What's special about the human language faculty?” Cognition 95 (2).

Spelke, E. (2003), “What Makes Us Smart? Core Knowledge and Natural Language”, en Gentner, D. & Goldin-Meadow, D. (eds.): Language in Mind. Advances in the Study of Language and Thought, The MIT Press, Cambridge, M.A., 277-312.




[1] The most general and simplistic reason for thinking this is that sensory neurons can be easily analogised to the input nodes in a connectionist model, output nodes can be analogised to the motor neurons and the hidden nodes can be analogised to the web of neural connections in our nervous systems [Braddon-Mitchell & Jackson, 2007: 223])
[2] The most straightforward data included the “distributed representation” used by the brain (held to be strong counter-evidence of the existence of discrete symbols) and the fact of “graceful degradation” (certainly counter-evidence of digital hardware).

No comments:

Post a Comment