Search This Blog

Thursday 27 April 2017

A Short Essay I wrote last year for a unit called "Models of Democracy" on Federalist 10 and Robert Dahl and Social Capital and Scale (before I read Peter Turchin, but whose ideas I pre-empted in my own abstract thinking)

In The Federalist 10, James Madison seeks to justify a particular kind of representative democracy (‘republican government’) on the basis that it offers the best chance of controlling the mischief of factions. Explain and evaluate Madison’s argument.

In The Federalist 10, James Madison argues that, as long as certain basic features of the human species obtain, there will be a division of society into “factions” with interests inimical to other factions and to the “public good”. His claim is that a republican government is the best palliative to this problem because it is the ultimate compromise: like a “pure democracy”, it can defeat minority factions “by regular vote”, and like a more oligarchical system, it has means to prevent a majority faction from gaining too much power.
In this essay, I express strong opposition to Madison’s arguments. My overall thesis is that, whether or not Madison’s arguments were justified pragmatically, they are badly flawed theoretical arguments. Firstly, I argue that he was almost entirely wrong about the faction-negating effects of size, because he ignored the role of cultural and economic unity in degrading the “mischief of factions”. This also undermines his absolute hostility to “pure democracy”, which is not fundamentally unstable in small communities or societies. Secondly, I argue that, while Madison is correct that inequality generates factions, he was seriously misguided about the inevitability of the kind of inequality that existed in his time, and wrong to overlook the simple ‘removing-the-cause’ strategy of increasing equality. Finally, since I disagree with Madison’s Platonic view that representatives chosen only from the aristocratic class can know the “public good”, I argue that factional uprisings to broaden representation are not always “improper or wicked”.

In The Federalist 10, James Madison identifies two possible types of solution to “the mischiefs of faction, “removing its causes” or “controlling its effects”, and argues that only the latter is viable. [Madison, 1787: 1]. He explains that there are two methods of carrying out the first type of solution – destroying liberty or making all citizens identical – and that both are completely untenable. Destroying liberty would be an unthinkable overstep, and the “second expedient” would be impossible, since “as long as the reason of man continues fallible, and he is at liberty to exercise it, different opinions will be formed” [1]. This leads him to the final inference that “the causes of faction cannot be removed and that relief is only to be sought in the means of controlling its effects” [2].
For Madison, the best way of controlling the effects of faction is, of course, a republican system – a system involving delegation of government “to a small number of citizens elected by the rest” over a very wide territory [2]. Madison’s central thesis seems to be that the republican system is the best compromise between a “pure democracy” (like Athens), which can defeat minority factions straightforwardly, and an oligarchy (more like Republican Rome), which opens up the possibility of weakening the power of majority factions. He illustrates this point by outlining the ways in which a republican system differs from a pure democracy. Whilst both are “popular governments” in some sense, a republic delegates government “to a small number of citizens”, and Madison believes this process will “refine and enlarge the public views” since the chosen citizens “will be least likely to sacrifice [the public interest] to temporary or partial considerations” [2-3].
The other difference between a pure democracy and the republic is that the republic is far larger. Madison believes this is a significant advantage for negating the mischiefs of factions, for two reasons: the greater number of citizens should “make it more difficult for vicious candidates to practise the vicious arts by which elections are too often carried”, and an extended sphere makes it “less probable that a majority of the whole will have a common motive to invade the rights of other citizens” [3].
As I explained in the introduction, I have several problems with Madison’s arguments, and one of the biggest concerns exactly this reasoning about the ideal size of the republic. As Robert Dahl writes in his excellent 2005 paper, “James Madison: Republican or Democrat?”, “if we consider the [argument about size] as an empirical proposition in political science […] two centuries of experience since then flatly contradicts his proposition” [Dahl, 2005: 445]. Madison went so wrong, I believe, because he ignored one key consideration from his calculation: the necessity of socio-cultural and economic unity– what Robert Putnam calls “social capital” [Putnam, 1993] – for any society which hopes to avoid factional dissension. The American Civil War broke out less than 80 years after Federalist 10 was published because there was a massive division of economic interests between the agricultural South, and the more mercantile North. Today, as Dahl himself points out, some of the most successful democratic societies – arguably the least faction-prone democratic societies – are ones with relatively small populations: “the three Scandinavian countries, together with Finland, the Netherlands, Switzerland, and New Zealand” [Dahl, 2005: 445].[1] As Dahl also notes, this correlation between smallness of polity and cohesion even extends to very small democratic communities. His own evidence for this comes from a 2004 analysis of town meetings in Vermont,[2] yet far more significant is the evidence from the massive anarchist literature on small-scale direct democracy: for example, the accounts of the communes in Revolutionary Catalonia, or contemporary examples of workplace democracy, such as that of the Mondragon Corporation in Spain.[3]
Madison’s failure to realise the complexities of the ‘size question’ is also what leads to his simplistic dismissal of “pure democracy”. The easier promotion of “social capital” in smaller democratic societies clearly gives part of the explanation as to why the direct democracy in 5th and early 4th Century Athens was able to function at all: Athens was a polity just small enough for its citizens to have a robust sense of civic purpose and unity of interest.
Of course, Madison was right that a larger jurisdiction increases diversity, and thereby probably vitiates the development of an impassioned majority faction,[4] but this only brings us to a bigger problem: that the whole argument is premised on a self-serving fatalism about inequality. After proclaiming that factions “are thus sown into the nature of man”, Madison suddenly brings up a very important truth about the role of inequality: “The most common and durable source of factions has been the various and unequal distribution of property”, which divides people “into different classes, actuated by different sentiments and views” [Madison, 1787: 1-2]. The reason he doesn’t see this as self-contradiction is perhaps that he took it for granted that increasing equality (somehow) means destroying liberty. But, whatever the case, it seems to me that this tells us something significant about the subtext of The Federalist 10: at its heart, the paper is an expression of Madison’s base fear that if the American democracy was too strong, it would undermine the interests of his faction, the landed aristocracy. Indeed, Madison’s remarks in the “Secret Debates of the Federal Constitution”, which also took place in 1787, reveal thoughts along exactly these lines: “In England, at this day, if elections were open to all classes of people, the property of landed proprietors would be insecure. [To prevent this] our government ought to secure the permanent interests of the country against innovation […] to protect the minority of the opulent against the majority” [as transcribed by Robert Yates, 1927 print].
As Noam Chomsky points out, Madison differs in this way from one of his main influences, Aristotle. Aristotle also worried about the poor in a democracy infringing upon the property rights of the rich, but he thought the solution was increasing equality [Chomsky, 2012: 237]. In fact, in book VI, Aristotle writes the following: “The true friend of the people should see that they not be too poor, for extreme poverty lowers the character of democracy; measures therefore should be taken which will give them lasting prosperity” [Aristotle, 1999: 147].
The extent of equality is, of course, the other major reason that the Scandinavian countries have such high social capital. It also gives us another part of the explanation as to why Athenian direct democracy could succeed at all: the Gini coefficient for the Athenian citizen population in late 4th Century Athens has been calculated at 0.708, “more equal than Florence in 1427 (0.788) or the USA in 1998 (0.794)” [Ober, 2010: 13].
This brings me to my final point of disagreement with Madison. I don’t, in fact, believe that all factional uprisings are “wicked or improper” [Madison, 1787: 5]. Indeed, I think that factional uprisings of a certain kind have, since 1787, made our society more just. The first two waves of the feminist movement were “factional”, as was the powerful labour activism of the early 20th Century, as well as the Civil Rights movement of the 1960s. Although there is always the danger of “an interested and overbearing majority”, in practice, I feel that an equally significant problem throughout history has been loosening the grip of the elites on the system, who, in reality, never possess the higher Platonic wisdom they claim.
Reference List

Aristotle (1999). The Politics, trans. Benjamin Jowett, Batoche Books, Kitchener.

Chomsky, Noam (2012). Power Systems: Conversations on Global Democratic Uprisings and the New Global Threats to U.S. Empire, Metropolitan Books, New York.

Clayton, Edward (2002). “Aristotle: The Politics”, Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Accessed from:
<http://www.iep.utm.edu/aris-pol/>

Dahl, Robert (2005). “James Madison: Republican or Democrat?”, Perspectives on Politics, 3(3): 439-448. Accessed from:
<http://www.jstor.org/stable/3689017>

Madison, James (1787). The Federalist 10, transcript from the National Archives Online Portal: http://www.ourdocuments.gov/doc.php?flash=true&doc=10&page=transcript.

Putnam, Robert (1993). Making Democracy Work, Princeton University Press.

Notes of the Secret Debates of the Federal Convention of 1787, transcribed by Robert Yates. Accessed from:
<http://avalon.law.yale.edu/18th_century/yates.asp>





[1] It should, of course, be noted that when talking about factions in today’s context, anachronism is inevitable. I think Dahl here is using “faction” to refer to extreme parties and separatist groups – perhaps Tea Partyers, Neo-nazis, communists, etc.
[2] In particular, Frank Bryan’s 2004 book Real Democracy: The New England Town Meeting and How it Works
[3] The best known of these accounts of 1936 Spain is, of course, George Orwell’s Homage to Catalonia.
[4] Mainstream political parties in big Western countries do their best to unite people, but even if they do, it is very often passionless, merely symbolic unity.

No comments:

Post a Comment